<%BANNER%>

The Discourse of Masculinity in Demosthenes 21 and Aeschines 1

Permanent Link: http://ufdc.ufl.edu/UFE0022264/00001

Material Information

Title: The Discourse of Masculinity in Demosthenes 21 and Aeschines 1
Physical Description: 1 online resource (54 p.)
Language: english
Publisher: University of Florida
Place of Publication: Gainesville, Fla.
Publication Date: 2008

Subjects

Subjects / Keywords: aeschines, attic, demosthenes, hubris, hubristes, hybris, hybristes, kinaidos, masculinity, meidias, oratory, timarchos
Classics -- Dissertations, Academic -- UF
Genre: Classical Studies thesis, M.A.
bibliography   ( marcgt )
theses   ( marcgt )
government publication (state, provincial, terriorial, dependent)   ( marcgt )
born-digital   ( sobekcm )
Electronic Thesis or Dissertation

Notes

Abstract: In the following chapters I will examine the spectrum of masculinity in ancient Athens. Men could be either too masculine or not masculine enough. It is useful to consider masculinity as a spectrum with proper manliness in the middle and deficient masculinity, represented by the kinaidos, and hyper-masculinity, represented by the hybristes on the ends. All men would have sought to portray themselves as hoplites, who represented proper masculinity as kinaidoi and hybristes represented the improper forms. After a brief introduction I will examine Demosthenes 21 for details about the hybristes. Demosthenes portrays his opponent as completely worthless to the city because he has allowed his masculinity to rage out of control. Unlike a man who keeps his masculinity in check, Meidias freely insults other citizens and disregards their rights. Additionally he disregards the demos' attempts to check his behavior and uses the courts to benefit himself rather than the city. For these reasons, Meidias? masculinity harms rather than helps the city, as it should. On the other end of the spectrum we find Timarchos, the defendant in Aeschines 1. Timarchos allows his lack of masculinity to control him. Instead of controlling himself, he is controlled by his desires. Because he is so addicted to physical pleasure, Timarchos prostitutes himself devours his inheritance and the city?s funds in his quest for satisfaction. While Meidias harms his fellow citizens for the sake of his own honor and amusement, Timarchos harms the city by robbing it to support his habits. These two men were both faulty in their masculinity, though in opposite ways, and each man was a danger to the city because he valued himself more than the city and lacked self-control.
General Note: In the series University of Florida Digital Collections.
General Note: Includes vita.
Bibliography: Includes bibliographical references.
Source of Description: Description based on online resource; title from PDF title page.
Source of Description: This bibliographic record is available under the Creative Commons CC0 public domain dedication. The University of Florida Libraries, as creator of this bibliographic record, has waived all rights to it worldwide under copyright law, including all related and neighboring rights, to the extent allowed by law.
Thesis: Thesis (M.A.)--University of Florida, 2008.
Local: Adviser: Wolpert, Andrew Oxman.

Record Information

Source Institution: UFRGP
Rights Management: Applicable rights reserved.
Classification: lcc - LD1780 2008
System ID: UFE0022264:00001

Permanent Link: http://ufdc.ufl.edu/UFE0022264/00001

Material Information

Title: The Discourse of Masculinity in Demosthenes 21 and Aeschines 1
Physical Description: 1 online resource (54 p.)
Language: english
Publisher: University of Florida
Place of Publication: Gainesville, Fla.
Publication Date: 2008

Subjects

Subjects / Keywords: aeschines, attic, demosthenes, hubris, hubristes, hybris, hybristes, kinaidos, masculinity, meidias, oratory, timarchos
Classics -- Dissertations, Academic -- UF
Genre: Classical Studies thesis, M.A.
bibliography   ( marcgt )
theses   ( marcgt )
government publication (state, provincial, terriorial, dependent)   ( marcgt )
born-digital   ( sobekcm )
Electronic Thesis or Dissertation

Notes

Abstract: In the following chapters I will examine the spectrum of masculinity in ancient Athens. Men could be either too masculine or not masculine enough. It is useful to consider masculinity as a spectrum with proper manliness in the middle and deficient masculinity, represented by the kinaidos, and hyper-masculinity, represented by the hybristes on the ends. All men would have sought to portray themselves as hoplites, who represented proper masculinity as kinaidoi and hybristes represented the improper forms. After a brief introduction I will examine Demosthenes 21 for details about the hybristes. Demosthenes portrays his opponent as completely worthless to the city because he has allowed his masculinity to rage out of control. Unlike a man who keeps his masculinity in check, Meidias freely insults other citizens and disregards their rights. Additionally he disregards the demos' attempts to check his behavior and uses the courts to benefit himself rather than the city. For these reasons, Meidias? masculinity harms rather than helps the city, as it should. On the other end of the spectrum we find Timarchos, the defendant in Aeschines 1. Timarchos allows his lack of masculinity to control him. Instead of controlling himself, he is controlled by his desires. Because he is so addicted to physical pleasure, Timarchos prostitutes himself devours his inheritance and the city?s funds in his quest for satisfaction. While Meidias harms his fellow citizens for the sake of his own honor and amusement, Timarchos harms the city by robbing it to support his habits. These two men were both faulty in their masculinity, though in opposite ways, and each man was a danger to the city because he valued himself more than the city and lacked self-control.
General Note: In the series University of Florida Digital Collections.
General Note: Includes vita.
Bibliography: Includes bibliographical references.
Source of Description: Description based on online resource; title from PDF title page.
Source of Description: This bibliographic record is available under the Creative Commons CC0 public domain dedication. The University of Florida Libraries, as creator of this bibliographic record, has waived all rights to it worldwide under copyright law, including all related and neighboring rights, to the extent allowed by law.
Thesis: Thesis (M.A.)--University of Florida, 2008.
Local: Adviser: Wolpert, Andrew Oxman.

Record Information

Source Institution: UFRGP
Rights Management: Applicable rights reserved.
Classification: lcc - LD1780 2008
System ID: UFE0022264:00001


This item has the following downloads:


Full Text

PAGE 1

1 THE DISCOURSE OF MASCULINITY IN DEMOSTHENES 21 AND AESCHINES 1 By SETH BOUTIN A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLOR IDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA 2008

PAGE 2

2 2008 Seth Boutin

PAGE 3

3 Familiae amicisque qui me semper sustinent

PAGE 4

4 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to thank first m y adviser A ndrew Wolpert and committee members Kostas Kapparis, and Jim Marks. This thesis is deeply indebted to them and their priceless help, and I am deeply indebted to the endless patience th ey have shown me. I would also like to acknowledge my classmates James Lohmar and Mega n Daly. Our discussions about our projects provided a chance for me to learn about subjects I otherwise would not have studied and an opportunity to test my own ideas against the sharp minds of my peers.

PAGE 5

5 TABLE OF CONTENTS page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS...............................................................................................................4 LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS.......................................................................................................... 6 ABSTRACT.....................................................................................................................................7 CHAP TER 1 INTRODUCTION....................................................................................................................9 2 DEMOSTHENES ORATION AGAINST MEIDIAS .............................................................17 3 AESCHINES ORATION AGAINST TIMARCHOS ..............................................................32 4 CONCLUSION..................................................................................................................... ..49 LIST OF REFERENCES...............................................................................................................52 BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH.........................................................................................................54

PAGE 6

6 LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS CQ Classical Quarterly G&R Greece and Rome HSCP Harvard Studies in Classical Philology JHS Journal of Hellenic Studies

PAGE 7

7 Abstract of Thesis Presen ted to the Graduate School of the University of Florida in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts THE DISCOURSE OF MASCULINITY IN DEMOSTHENES 21 AND AESCHINES 1 By Seth Boutin May 2008 Chair: Andrew Wolpert Major: Classical Studies In the following chapters I will examine the spectrum of masculinity in ancient Athens. Men could be either too masculine or not masculine enough. It is useful to consider masculinity as a spectrum with proper manliness in the mi ddle and deficient masculinity, represented by the kinaidos, and hyper-masculinity, represented by the hybristes on the ends. All men would have sought to portray themselves as hoplites, who represented proper masculinity as kinaidoi and hybristes represented the improper forms. After a brief introduction I will examine Demosthenes 21 for details about the hybristes Demosthenes portrays his opponent as completely wo rthless to the city because he has allowed his masculinity to rage out of control. Un like a man who keeps his masculinity in check, Meidias freely insults other citizens and disregards their rights. Additionally he disregards the demos attempts to check his behavior and uses the c ourts to benefit himself rather than the city. For these reasons, Meidias masculinity harms rather than helps the city, as it should. On the other end of the spectrum we find Timarchos, the defendant in Aeschines 1. Timarchos allows his lack of masculinity to control him. Instead of controlling himself, he is controlled by his desires. Because he is so ad dicted to physical pleasure, Timarchos prostitutes himself devours his inheritance a nd the citys funds in his quest for satisfaction. While Meidias harms his fellow citizens for the sake of his own honor and amusement, Timarchos harms the

PAGE 8

8 city by robbing it to support his habits. These two men were both faulty in their masculinity, though in opposite ways, and each man was a danger to the city because he valued himself more than the city and lacked self-control.

PAGE 9

9 CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION Ober begins his discussion of De mosthenes 21 with an explanation of the coercive and discursive paradigms of power (1994: 86-87). In the coercive model, power stems from the ability to deploy physical force. Power is centrali zed in the state, and the state reserves the sole authority to use force legitimately at home via police actions and abroad through wars. In this model, power represses individuals and behaviors that harm the laws or sovereignty of the state. The discursive paradigm, on the othe r hand, is not concerned with force per se, but defines power instead as the ability to gain ones desires. The discursive paradi gm recognizes that force can be used as power, but rejects the notion that force is the only way to exert power. Instead, it focuses on how ideas and assumptions legitimize the use of force, therefore standing as the true sources of power. For example, if we were to apply the coercive and discursive paradigms to Medieval Europe, the coercive paradigm might focus on how a king could send soldiers to enforce his will on a village in his realm, while the discursive paradigm would focus on the social concept of the divine right of kings as the source of the pow er that only sometimes manifests itself as physical force. A close look at Athens immediately reveals that the discursi ve paradigm is superior to the coercive model as a tool for analyzing its soci al institutions. There was no police force to apprehend criminals; there were no designa ted prosecutors to pursue them in court.1 The state did not monopolize the legitimate use of force, though the democracy did monopolize the right to legitimize coercion among private citizens. On ly after winning his case could one citizen enforce his will on another, and these cases took pl ace in public courts before citizen juries. To win his case a litigant often presented himself as living in accordance with common mores while 1 For more on self help see Hunter 120-124.

PAGE 10

10 his opponent subverted them. If a litigant knew how to manipulat e public opinions and stereotypes to his advantage, he could win the le gal right to use force. Therefore the Athenian legal system linked knowledge with the legitimate use of force as power. Extant speeches provide a window into how Athenians thought of themselves because litigants argued their cases from cu ltural ideals rather than realities.2 Ancient Athenian litigants, like modern politicians, attempted to appease their audiences by appealing to their opinions of how life should have worked, rather than to th eir knowledge of how the world actually was. Oratory depended more on how well it was recei ved by an audience of common people for its success than did any other source. Therefore, th ese speeches are an indispensable source to help reveal common sentiments held by average Athenian citizens. Comedy and tragedy were as accessible to a pub lic audience as oratory, but they did not aim at winning a case in which a nything from personal honor to life itself might be at stake. Instead they aimed to entertain, which means that they did not face the same rigid standards of ideological compliance that oratory did. Philo sophy also reveals valuable information about public ideals, but because philosophers argued about the way things should have been in their own opinions rather than in th e public opinion, they are also le ss useful than oratory. Other genres, such as history, touch upon common ideo logy at points, but are never more than tangentially related. For these r easons, though all extant literatu re is useful in one way or another, oratory is by far best suit ed to reveal public ideologies. Orators regularly manipulated public ideals concerning masculin ity to their advantage. This tendency is not surprising: because only men were citizens masculinity was rarely separated from civic issues. The link between citizensh ip and manhood cannot be overstated. To be a 2 Herman 1994: 106; Hunter 5-6; Ober 1989: 37.

PAGE 11

11 good citizen and to be a good man were synonymous in almost every case. Therefore, to understand the Athenian democracy we must first attempt to understand masculinity in Athens. This study is valuable today because the Atheni an democracy was the first democracy, and to understand the roots of modern democracy we must look to its ancestor in Attica. The results of Athenian ideals concerning men and government have taken a long time to fall out of favor. For example, even up to the foundations of our ow n nation the link between full citizenship and masculinity was so basic that it was not until th e last century that women received suffrage. With such a strong link between masculinity and citizenship, there had to be a model for proper masculinity, and the hoplite provided th at model for the ideal man. A hoplite was physically strong enough to stand shoulder to shoulder with his peers and fight off a common enemy. A hoplite also had a sufficient comman d of his mind and emotions to stand his ground without fleeing the possibility of death. Even though the thetes were the force that maintained the Athenian empire, the hoplite remained the ideal man.3 Because the orators recognized that the hoplite embodied the masculine ideal, they addr essed their audiences as if each member were a hoplite, though as we have seen above only about one third of the demos was of hoplite status.4 This trope illustrates the points given above: oratory reveals cultura l ideals rather th an realities, and the cultural ideal for masculinity was the hoplite. While the hoplite provided a model for ideal ma sculinity, there were models for deficient masculinity, as well. The character type for insufficient masculinity was the kinaidos. A kinaidos was uncontrolled in his sexual practices. There has been some recent debate of the precise meaning of the term kinaidos. Winkler, among many others, ho lds that while the term is 3 Cartledge argues that the thetes were the power behind the democracy and made up a huge portion of the demos yet even thetes preferred to conceive of them selves as hoplites (61-65). 4 For several examples of rich litigants portraying th emselves as hoplites, see Ober 1989: 204 and 207.

PAGE 12

12 complex one of its central features is passivity toward penetration.5 According to his model, the kinaidos is certainly unrestrained, but what places him so far outside of the realm of acceptable masculinity is his desire to be penetrated, or in the zero-sum language often used to describe ancient Athens, his desire to lose. Davidson rejects this Foucauldian model because it often emphasizes phallocentric interpretations.6 According to Davidson, kinaidos does not necessarily have connotations of passivity or penetration, but instead is a term th at denotes a complete l ack of restraint. He adduces several examples that support his clai ms, including examples from the animal kingdom in which animals that were thought to be especially sexually active were so branded. A kinaidos was not necessarily a man who enjoyed being pe netrated but a man whose desires were as insatiable as a leaky jar. Th ese observations on the uses of kinaidos that obviously do not fit the phallocentric model are quite helpful. Davidson s efforts to unseat the penetrator/penetrated model fall somewhat short, however, especially as he attempts to explain terms like wide-anused ( euryproktoi ) and cistern-anused ( lakkoproktoi ) in terms of insatiabil ity rather than anal penetration. The combination of a lack of constraint a nd the desire to be penetrated emasculates the kinaidos. Winkler proposes that the hoplite and the kinaidos served as training wheels for masculine ideology. The idea of the kinaidos as a training wheel work s, but the hoplite can hardly be seen as the other training wheel when instead he was the ideal that men sought to emulate. Instead of Winklers training wheel analogy, it makes more sense to consider 5 Winkler 185. 6 Davidson 167-182.

PAGE 13

13 masculinity as a spectrum. The kinaidos represents one end of the spectrum while the hoplite occupied the middle. The spectrum analogy for masculinity mirrors po ints of middling ideo logy. According to Morris model, most Athenian men ascribed to middling ideology, which assumed that all citizens were similar in thei r mindsets, birth, and assets.7 An ideal middling man had as much money as he needed, but not enough to be extrav agant. Likewise a middling man would be a hoplite, and would partic ipate in the democracy in order to support his city. Men who fell outside the middling region could be dangerous to the democracy. For instance, men who were either too rich or too poor coul d be dangerous because their exce ssive wealth provided means to harm the demos or their poverty made them desperate. Obviously to a degree middling ideology was a dramatic fiction. Some citizens had mu ch more money, education, land, and influence than others, but rhetors and litig ants addressed their audiences as if they were middling men nonetheless. Masculinity provided another category in which men who fell outside of the middle were considered dangerous, some because they were not masculine enough, others because they were hyper-masculine. While the kinaidos occupies the end of the spectrum reserved fo r the under-masculine man, the over-masculine hybristes occupies the opposite posit ion. Both ends of the spectrum were to be avoided in favor of the hoplite ideal between them. As frightening as the image of the kinaidos was, the hybristes could be just as dangerous to the demos. Demosthenes uses the term hybris or one of its cognates 112 times in a speech that is onl y 227 sections long. He reiterates Meidias hybris over and over to demonstrat e the pattern of behavior Meidias has exhibited over the course of his life. Hybris was indeed a serious offense and carried as a penalty exile or even 7 Morris 114-119.

PAGE 14

14 execution for the Athenian unlucky enough to be convicted for it. The definitions of hybris surviving from antiquity conflict and do not provide a clear understanding of exactly what it was. Recent works by MacDowell, Fisher, and Ca irns have helped clarify the issue. MacDowell searches for a comprehensive definition of hybris by examining some of the less conventional uses, for instance, when it is applied to animals or bodies of water. H ybris is often a characteristic of the youthful and the wealthy, and many examples of hybris involve violence and dishonor.8 It is not a religious offence unle ss it is committed specifically against a deity, and thus concludes that hybris is having energy or power a nd misusing it self-indulgently.9 Fisher also examines the myriad uses of hybris and agrees with MacDowells assessment that it did not have anything to do with religion unless it was committed against a god. In contrast to MacDowells wide de finition, however, Fisher defines hybris as an act of intentional insult meant to inflict shame and dishonor on others.10 Fisher argues that even if the victim of hybris is only loosely implied, hybris is not hybris without a victim, and likewise transgressions involving self-indulgent use of power and thinking big cannot be hybris unless they target a victim. Cairns disagrees with Fisher and claims that hybris can be a synonym for mega phronein which he translates as thinking big.11 He provides several convincing examples of how hybris and thinking big seem to be s ynonymous. Cairns also discusses prohairesis which can be translated as predisposition. A ccording to his analysis the pr edisposition toward hubristic acts 8 MacDowell 1976: 15-16. 9 MacDowell 1976: 21. 10 Fisher 1992: 148. 11 Cairns 10-17.

PAGE 15

15 often arises from an over-infla ted self image, which is a problem shared both by the young and the wealthy. Cairns disagrees with Fishers estimation that hybris must have a specific victim, but affirms both MacDowells and Fishers findings that hybris is not an inherently religious offense. The most pertinent portion of this artic le for the present study addresses the relationship between hybris and masculinity. Here Cairns claims that there is a clear link between the powerful forces of masculinity and a headstrong sp irit which values self over others and rejects external restraint.12 Therefore hybris is the fault that results fr om an abundance of masculine energy and a lack of restraint. Cairns seems to be correct that thinking big can encompass hybris and he acknowledges Fishers valid points about hybris having a victim in most cases, so for the most part I will accept Cairns definition. While Cairns definition is useful, however, I would not claim that it is perfect. Recent debate on the meaning of hybris and the term kinaidos, as well, demonstrates how multifaceted these words could be. While th ere were core meanings for each term, one relating to an overinflated self image leading to demeaning other people a nd the other relating to sexual deviance, beyond such generalizations even ancient Athenians may have disagreed about the precise definition of each term. Because the charge of hybris comes up so often, Demosthenes 21 is an excellent speech in which to examine hybris as an anti-masculine quality. Demosthenes attempts to demonstrate throughout the speech that Meidias is hubristic, and in the process he provides a great deal of useful information on the place of a hybristes in the city. A hubristic citizen is completely useless to the demos because he puts himself ahead of the need s of the city in every situation. In addition, hybris does not translate into any corresponding vi rtue, such as bravery. Therefore, a 12 Cairns 24.

PAGE 16

16 hybristes is not a man who is too bold and daring but one whose masculinity has become so defective from his lack of self-control that the citizen body must fight him off. Perhaps the best case to examine the opposite end of the spectrum, that of the kinaidos, is Aeschines 1. The irony here is that Aeschines never calls Timarchos a kinaidos directly, although he implies it constantly. Timarchos wa s completely unrestrained in his habits and behavior, and he was frequently the object of penetration. No matter whose definition of kinaidos we use, the term applies to Timarchos as Aeschines portrays him. Timarchos, like Meidias, also represented a threat to the city. While Meidias threat ened the city directly with his insolence, Timarchos was dangerous because he would not hesitate to rob from the city to support himself. Both the kinaidos and the hybristes lack restraint, and it is that characteristic that separates them from the hoplite. The hoplite remains in formation, puts the city before himself, and generally embodies masculine ideals. In this thesis I will examin e how Demosthenes and Aeschines manipulate masculine id eals of the hoplite versus the hybristes and the kinaidos to promote themselves and attack their enemies. These speeches provide chances to see how proper masculinity was set against masculinity de ficient either for bei ng too masculine or too effeminate. These specific orations provide perf ect examples for how knowledge of the negative extremes of masculinity could be very powerful indeed.

PAGE 17

17 CHAPTER 2 DEMOSTHENES ORATION AGAINST MEIDIAS Against Meidias provid es a chance to examine self-rest raint and moderation set against the negative hyper-mascu line quality of hybris In this chapter I will examine how Demosthenes depicts his self-restraint as conforming to common masculine ideals and Meidias hybris as subverting them. Before analyzing the text we mu st settle questions about its goal and delivery that affect the present discussion. Whether or not the case was delivered and what charge was used affect how we must read the text. I will argue that the case was delivered and that the charge was a probole for offences during the festival. We will then turn to the details Demosthenes presents to prove that Meidias is usel ess to the city. Because he allows his lack of self-control to sabotage his masc ulinity and turn him into a hybristes Meidias not only assaults the honor and rights of his fellow citizens, but even harms the demos Furthermore, Meidias hybris does not bring with it any concomitant benefits. Instead, because he has allowed his masculinity to move out of the middle of the spectrum and into the range of the hybristes he has become entirely useless. In the year 347/6 Demosthenes resumed pros ecution of a wealthy Athenian named Meidias for an offence that occurred at the festival of Dionysos in the summer of 348. According to Demosthenes, Meidias struck him in the theater while he was serving as a chorus producer. He first pursued the case as a probole, a procedure immediately following the festival for infractions committed during it. This procedure took place befo re the Ekklesia, but did not carry with it any penalty beyond censure. Two years later he re sumed the case by initia ting a public suit which could carry a heavy penalty. At the beginning of the speech that he composed for trial, Demosthenes explains that he l odged a public suit against Meid ias so that everyone would know that he was acting out of Athens best interest s and not attacking Meidias for personal gain.

PAGE 18

18 To form an accurate interpretation of this speech, we must examine two controversial topics. There has been disagreement about the procedure Demosthenes used to bring the dispute to court. First, some have cl aimed that he initiated a suit of hybris while others that he either brought a suit for impropriety at a festival or it remained a probole. The actual legal charge and the procedure which Demosthenes used to prosecut e Meidias are important since they affect our understanding of his rhetorical arguments. Fo r instance, if Meidias was not charged with hybris why does the case read like a graphe hybreos ? Whether this was a graphe hybre s or a probole, we must resolve if it was delivered at all. Because one of the reasons Demosthenes may not have delivered the case is that he did not think it would have been successful, whether or not the case was delivered affects how we must read the strength or wea kness of the case. If this case was not delivered it is a less reli able source for masculine ideology. Harris argues that the case be gan as a probole before the Ek klesia immediately after the festival, but then was next pursued as a graphe hybreos when presented to the court. Demosthenes, however, lists some of his options, and even mentions that Meidias will claim that he should have prosecuted him with a private case to recover damages and a graphe hybreos for the assault (25-28). MacDowell, as a result, concludes that the probole was indeed the proper name for a suit which came to the court after init ially lodged as such before the Ekklesia (1990: 13-17). Similarly, the apagoge is another example of an initial procedure that lent its name to resulting legal action. Demosthenes accuses Meidias of hybris constantly throughout the speech, but he states that the graphe hybreos was a suit he could have but did not bring. Furthermore, because of the precedent for calling proceedings by their initial phases there is reason enough to accept MacDowells interpretation that this was not a graphe hybreos as Harris claims, but a probole for offences committed during the festival.

PAGE 19

19 Many doubt whether Demosthenes ever brought Meidias to court because Aeschines alleges that he sold the case for thirty mnai.1 Aeschines comments have often been interpreted to mean that Demosthenes agreed to settle the cas e out of court. Scholars also infer from internal evidence that the speech was never completed. As MacDowe ll sums up, the laws presented in sections 94 and 113 have no explanation and seem to be irrelevant; Demosthenes twice uses the metaphor of life as an eranos loan without acknowledging his repetition; and in consecutive sections Demosthenes repeats a list of Meidias supporters as if he had not mentioned them before (1990: 23-28). Harris argues that the stylistic problems are insignificant and calls into question the truthfulness of comments Ae schines expressed in court.2 Since the scholiasts do not express concern over Demosthenes style, Harris doubts that we lack sufficient reasons to call into question the delivery of the speec h. Additionally, since so much time elapsed between the two cases, most jurors would not have remembered th e case against Meidias, and therefore Aeschines was free to take liberties with the truth. Fi nally, if Demosthenes dropped the case before the anakrisis, then he could not have wr itten a speech that displayed clear knowledge of Meidias defensive strategies. If, on the othe r hand, he dropped th e case after the anakrisis, he would have suffered atimia Surely Aeschines would have men tioned that Demosthenes suffered atimia especially if it was a result of the very case which he had alread y mentioned. So, one can safely conclude that 1 Aes. 3.52 : (and you know already about the affair with Meidias and the blows he received while acting as a choregos in the orchestra, and that he sold for thirty mnai the hybris against himself and the decision of the demos in which they convicted Meidias). 2 Harris 1989: 117-136; cf. Ober 1994: 85-108.

PAGE 20

20 Demosthenes did not drop the case. Harris o ffers a simpler explanation for Aeschines statement. Because both the prosecutor and the defendant had the opportunity to propose penalties following the conviction, Aeschines could either have b een referring to a penalty that Meidias had proposed and paid following his conv iction or the penalty that Demosthenes had proposed. Since Demosthenes reiterates that Medias deserves death, it is hard to imagine that Demosthenes proposed a penalty of less than a single talent, but it is not impossible. I believe that the speech was delivered at trial for a probole against Meidias and that he was convicted but only forced to pay a penalty of 30 mnai. Internal evidence supports this outcome. Demosthenes lists three other ex amples of men who have been convicted by probole, one of whom had to pay a fine, one died before he could be senten ced, and the third was condemned (175-183). Since the offender w ho was condemned whipped free people while marching in a procession, he went be yond impropriety and into the realm of hybris even more than Meidias had. Although Demosthenes uses thes e examples to prove that Meidias deserves a heavy penalty, only one involved a capital penalty. Therefore it is reasonable to infer that the probole usually resulted in only a fine. Aeschines probably referred to the penalty that the jury imposed upon Meidias as a payment in order to attribute pecuniary motives to Demosthenes. Demosthenes paints Meidias as the worst sort of man: one with no inclination to do good but a constant need to act against the best interests of hi s city and fellow citizens. This portrait is clearest when Demosthenes contrasts Meidias acti ons with those that he considers proper. The goal of each detail is to prove repeatedly that Meidias contravenes the behavior prescribed by Athenian popular morality; particularly that he lacks self-restraint and moderation. This entire speech aims to show that Meidias was a hubristi c man, a coward, and a threat to the democracy

PAGE 21

21 in his old age, the time of life when a man conventionally should have been at his most restrained and circumspect. The core of this case stems from a punch, but Demosthenes never allows for the possibility that this punch was onl y a punch: instead it was hybris There are elements to hybris that go beyond merely striking another. What sets a hubris tic attack apart from an average attack can be almost imperceptible details about the transgre ssors demeanor, how he speaks, whether he strikes on the face or elsewhere (72). Meidias exhibited signs of hybris and Demosthenes claims that he acted with self restraint ( s phrona) by deciding to take the cas e to court when he could have hit Meidias back (74). Modern readers may be unimpressed with the severity offense, and indeed Demosthenes seems to be defending his honor when he discusses examples of hybris in which the victims responded more vigorously than he did (70-76). In two cases, th e man who had been the victim of hybris killed his attacker in response to offenses that occurred at private parties where the participants were drinking. Demost henes, by contrast, was a victim of hybris in public at the hands of a sober and insolent aggressor. St rong drink is one of the mitigating factors for hubristic behavior; so because Meidias was sober wh en he attacked Demosthenes, this incident demonstrates the sort of man he is even without outside influences. On the one hand, Demosthenes defends his own masculine honor by sympathizing with those who were not as restrained as he and killed those who dishonored them. On the other hand, he delicately avoids the uncomfortable suspicion that fear prevented him from resp onding to a physical attack more aggressively by subtly praising his own self-rest raint, thereby turning his own possible weakness into strength of character. Indeed, how could anyone question the strength of Demosthenes character when he chose to act on behalf of the la ws rather than respond to force with force?

PAGE 22

22 Cohen argues that some level of violence was a common and acceptable part of elite feuds.3 In his view, the law courts served as an open forum in which private enmities between elite members of Athenian society were played out in front of juries. Because violence, along with drunkenness, sexual rivalry, and verbal insults were a we ll-known part of disputes among the elite, the prosecutor in a case of violence often had to prove not only that he had been attacked but also that the violence he had suffered mer ited a conviction an d its accompanying penalty. According to Cohens analysis, De mosthenes found himself in a no-win situation because this speech betrayed tw o facts which were fundamentally at odds. On the one hand, Demosthenes was a member of the same leisured class as Meidias and participated in the agonistic struggle for honor. On the other hand, he claims that he did the right thing by taking the case to court rather than res ponding with violence. In Cohen s view the jury would not have sympathized with Demosthenes position. Theref ore, on the basis of Aeschines remarks cited above and his own ideas about the nature of violence in Athens, Cohen concludes that Demosthenes settled the case out of court. As we have already seen, however, there was no way for Demosthenes to drop his case without suffering atimia so Cohens conclusions based on this case are suspect. Herman, by contrast, argues that violence wa s in no way an acceptable part of Athenian society.4 Herman contrasts the ideal of instant an d disproportionate revenge and the ideal of self-restraint and legal recourse. He proposes that the civilized ideal had won out completely and the primitive ideal, which would have required Demosthenes to hit Meidias back immediately, 3 Cohen 93-101; cf. Fisher 1998: 68-97. 4 See Herman 1993, 1994, 2006.

PAGE 23

23 no longer held any weight.5 If violence was wholly unacceptable Meidias actions would have been reprehensible, and because Demosthenes had won the initial probole it is reasonable to assume that he would have won before a jury, as well. If Herman is right about the unacceptable nature of violence, however, Demosthenes comment s that seem to explain why he did not react more violently and quickly make less sense. Furthermore, if the punch were sufficient for a conviction Demosthenes would have focused more on it, so Hermans analysis is also flawed. Ober provides a nuanced analysis of these issues that does not suffer from the same problems as those of Cohen and Herman. Ober cl aims that standard ethi cs require instant and disproportionate revenge, while coop erative ethics require a victim to take his case to court and forego personal vengeance in favor of public redre ss. According to Ober these two ideologies worked together. While cooperative ethics took precedence in public disputes, standard ethics were still at work in private situations. Cooperative ethics dominated public matters because through that system of values citizens could obt ain equality through the laws though they did not have equality of means. Obers ideas are most useful in analyzing Demosthenes 21. If these two sets of ethical standards operated simultaneous ly we can understand why Demosthenes provided a mild apology for his actions, yet was still able to gain a conv iction worth 30 mnai. Furthermore if these dueling ideologies were both current, as Ober claims, then it makes sense that Demosthenes spends so much time through this speech on Meidias crimes against the city and her other citizens and so little on the punch itself. Two prior incidents relate closely to the actua l charge lodged against Meidias and concern men, who were still allowed to compete as choristers, even though they had neglected to perform their military service (58-60). Although their co mpetitors were angry at them for illegally 5 Herman 1994:102.

PAGE 24

24 competing, the legal choregoi were so pious and metrioi or moderate, that they did not interrupt the festival to prevent their unlawful compe titors from participating. Meidias embodies the opposite of this ideal: he does not think e nough of the festival, nor the laws, nor the demos nor even Dionysos to restrain himself from acco sting Demosthenes for little or no reason whatsoever.6 Where others refused to disturb the fes tival for their own benefit, Meidias must commit hybris for no benefit beyond his own pleasure. De mosthenes suggests that an acquittal will also set a dangerous precedent for future chor isters and harm the fairness of the competition. Thus, he renders the dispute to be not just abou t a punch, but an issue that really does merit a jurys attention. Tampering with dramatic competitions was only one of Meidias crimes. Demosthenes reiterates that Meidias lifelong villainy should help to convic t him before reading a list of his crimes to the jury (128). Demosthenes claims th at he would be worried if Meidias had lived an otherwise restrained and moderate lifestyle and had committed hybris against him alone. If that had been the case Demosthenes would not have b een able to convince th e jury of Meidias crime. As things do stand, however, Demosthenes claims that he is concerned that, since Meidias has committed so many other serious crimes, the jury might think Demosthenes presumptuous for prosecuting him for such a sma ll one (129). This sec tion provides a perfect segue into the list of offences while it acknowledges and plays on the lightness of the offence at hand, making that complaint against Demosthenes case seem slightly ridiculous. Of course the list of offences does not survive, but we may assume that each one of them followed the rhetorical plan of the rest of the speech and served to demonstrate both Meidias 6 61:

PAGE 25

25 lack of self-restraint and gene rally immoderate behavior. In addition these offences strengthen Demosthenes case that Meidias deserves enmity from the jury because of his life of hybris Demosthenes seeks to show that, even if the punch he received was not significant in itself, the jury should take this opportunity to punish a man who has earned it not only by punching a rival at a festival, but in ev ery aspect of his life. Demosthenes introduces the metaphor of lif e as a loan to demonstrate how the demos should treat men like Meidias. Demosthenes firs t uses the metaphor that if a man has been moderate and helpful he deserves to be treate d that way in return (101). If a man has been forceful and inconsiderate to his fellow citizens he deserves that same treatment himself. When he has described life as a loan Demosthenes addr esses himself to Meidias directly, dramatically telling him that he has accrued in terest on the latter so rt of loan. Demosthenes uses the metaphor again to suggest that a man who is shameless and hubristic ( ) deserves to be repaid in kind (185). The loan metaphor reinforces the legitimacy of a serious penalty in return for what the jury may have been tempted to view as minor crime. In addition the repetition of the lo an metaphor seems to fit in both pl aces. Demosthenes first uses the metaphor before he lists Meidias offences, and repeats it after. It is possible that he used the metaphor twice so that he could make sure that the image of life as a lo an was already in the dikasts minds before he listed Meidias offences, and he reiterated the metaphor at the end of the speech when Meidias contributions to such a loan would be perfectly clear. Perhaps the most heinous exam ple of Meidias overweening hybris is how he treated the arbitrator Straton (83-101). Straton, a poor older man without politic al ambitions, was the arbitrator for a case between Demosthenes and Me idias that took place years earlier. Straton ruled in favor of Demosthenes by default when Meid ias did not appear for the case. Meidias first

PAGE 26

26 tried unsuccessfully to bribe Strat on to overturn his ruling, then he us ed political trickery to bring a case against Straton in his absence and have him disfranchised though the man had done nothing more than justly perfor m his duties as an arbitrator While Demosthenes may be distorting details of the disput e between Straton and Meidias,7 this anecdote holds two key features: the most important point was that Meidias was a threat to every Athenian citizen, but in addition Demosthenes uses the ages of the part ies involved to make a multi-layered point. When Straton came to the platform, he did not do so to testify. Because he had suffered atimia, he was not allowed to prov ide testimony before a jury. Meidias misused his own citizenship rights to deprive Straton of his. De mosthenes calls on the deepest pathos possible to illustrate the danger Meidias poses to the demos (95-97). The jury could easily sympathize with Straton: he was a poor man, like many of them would have been; he had served on military campaigns when called up for service, as they had; Straton was an upright citizen who had refused a bribe and instead of being rewarded for his integrity he was depr ived of his citizenship rights. An average Athenian mans citizenship rights were a main source of pride, and a poor man held his equality under the laws as tightly as a rich man held his personal honor.8 Meidias ability and willingness to use his wealth, power, and influence to deprive an average man of what he held most dear would have been one of the most damning points in De mosthenes oration. As Demosthenes made this point Straton stood nearby as visible proof of the results of Meidias behavior. 7 According to MacDowells reading of section 91, Straton lo st his appeal before a jury, which implies that he was not as blameless as Demosthenes claims. Whether he rela tes the story accurately or not the point of the story remains the same. 8 Ober 1994: 98.

PAGE 27

27 To be an arbitrator Straton must have been at least sixt y years old. Demosthenes calls Straton up to the platform in order to show clearly the difference between an older man who knew how to behave properly and Meidias who still behaved as a child. Though he was younger than Meidias, Demosthenes portrays himself as wise beyond his years while Meidias has failed to grow up. Demosthenes brings up age again wh en he claims that he is thirty-two while Meidias is perhaps a bit younger than fifty (154) Harris has argued very convincingly that Demosthenes could not have been as young as th irty-two, but was probabl y closer to thirtyeight.9 Harris disagrees with those who claim this wa s a scribal error and attributes this lie to Demosthenes desire to make his own liturgical record seem much better than Meidias. Ober agrees with Harris estimation but adds that Demosthenes may also be subtly comparing himself to one of the young men mentioned above who de fended himself by killing the older man who committed hybris against him.10 I would add that Demosthenes makes age an issue in an attempt to draw a comparison between himself and Meid ias. Although Demosthenes is a young man, he acts with self restraint, a characteristic more typical of older me n, while Meidias acts like a youth rather than a man of his more advanced years. Since youth was often regarded as a contributing factor in hybris when Demosthenes accuses Meidias of acting like a youth (e.g., 18, 131, 201) he is also attempting to add cred ence to his allegations of hybris against an older man. Of course, Meidias not only acts like a youth bu t is also very wea lthy, one of the other primary causes of hybris But Meidias wealthy hybris exceeds that of other men. Most rich men publicly submitted to the decisions of the demos even if they priv ately reviled them. Demosthenes shows that Meidias cannot even do that as he discusses his beha vior after the initial 9 Harris 1989: 24-26. 10 Ober 1994: 96.

PAGE 28

28 probole. Most men would have toned down their actio ns after a public censur e of that sort, but Meidias does the opposite (199). Instead Meidia s now more than ever speaks before the Ekklesia and proposes laws so th at he can show that he was not harmed by the decision of the Ekklesia. Meidias poor behavior in the Ekklesia also demonstrates his hybris. Demosthenes states that he is violent, shameless, a nd that he thinks big ( 201). In the context of his arrogance before the Ekklesia, Meidias shames the demos by thinking big when he should submit to their disapproval. Here there is a so lid link between thinking big and hybris As Demosthenes lists Meidias faults at 201 he does not mention hybris while he does mention thinking big. If we accept that thinking big and hybris can be synonymous, as Cairns claims, this usage both fits Cairns definition and Fishers de finition, which requires the intent to shame. By this point in the speech, members of the jury must have b een tempted to convict Meidias if for no other reason than to prove he was no better than they and Demosthenes and Straton. One would be tempted to believe that a man bold enough to punch Demosthenes in the face in public and disregard the demos would be us eful to the city in other ways, perhaps as a brave soldier who would scorn enemy battle lines as he scorns social norms at home. But we should not be surprised when we find that Demosthenes does not allow his opponent a single redeeming quality. Demosthenes introduces Meidia s as a soldier and rela tes the following story about his service in the cavalr y on a campaign to Argoura (132-135). He brought with him such fancy items, like golden cups, expensive clothes, and a silver saddle, that his fellow cavalrymen taunted him. The mockery so enraged Meidias th at he accused his fellow soldiers before the Ekklesia upon his return. This, at least, is how Demosthenes cl aims to have heard the story while serving as a hoplite. Meidias deficiency as a sold ier does not end with pampering

PAGE 29

29 himself and attacking his colleagues. After di scussing Meidias use of his wealth for his personal luxury rather than for the benefit of the c ity the charge becomes cowardice (160-167). Demosthenes asserts that Meidias volunteered for a trierarchy in order to avoid serving in the cavalry again. When the call for cavalry was rescinded, however, Meidias elected to send a metic in his place instead of lead ing his own trireme. Demosthene s calls this behavior unmanly cowardice. The charge of unmanliness is re peated in section 172, this time set alongside wickedness and evil.11 Because Meidias is useless as a sold ier, his masculinity is suspect. One cannot call the boldness necessary to punch a rival in the face before witnesses courage if that same boldness does not translate into success in battle. These anec dotes prove that Meidias has a prohairesis or predisposition, towards hybris alone, and no propensity for courage. With a predisposition for hybris and the wealth and will to indulge his inclinations Meidias is not only completely useless to the city but is a serious danger, as well. It is also significant that Demosthenes se rved as a hoplite while Meidias was in the cavalry. As we have seen the hoplite is the id eal form of Athenian masculinity, so it is no accident that Demosthenes mentions that he was in that branch of the military while his opponent served in the cavalry, the branch dominated by the elite. Demosthenes rev eals his own status as a hoplite for two reasons. First, he portrays hims elf as the ideal man willing to fight side by side with his fellow citizens; second as a hoplite he w ould have been physically strong. The contrast between the image of Meidias who was bold, ye t cowardly, and Demosthenes who was modest and willing to stand with his fe llow citizens would have been a powerful one to the jury. Also, as a hoplite, Demosthenes would have been strong enough to defend himself against Meidias, in theory at least. Because he could have defended himself against the bully physically but instead 11 160: ; 172:

PAGE 30

30 chose to take the case before a jury proves that it was self-restraint alone, rather than fear, that prevented Demosthenes from fighting back immediately. Demosthenes record as a hoplite did have at least one small blemish. Euktemon prosecuted Demosthenes for desertion, allegedly at Meidias bidding as retribution for this probole (103). Demosthenes does not deal with this case when he first brings it up, but says only that he did not need to answer the ch arge since the man w ho brought it suffered atimia for failing to proceed with the case. He indicates that Meidias would attempt to destroy anyone who sought justice from him.12 Therefore while Meidias paid others to prosecute Demosthenes for desertion for selfish motives, Demosthenes would consider himself a deserter from the battle lines of justice if he did not continue prosecuti ng Meidias in the face of such hardship.13 If the jury has accepted Demosthenes account of events up to this point they can hardly help but agree that to prosecute Meidias would be equivalent to fightin g for justice, especially given his ability to destroy less wealthy and powerful men like Strato n. The metaphor of Demosthenes as a soldier in the ranks of justice reinforces the image of Demosthenes as a hoplite and the corresponding point that he stands with the demos and is strong enough to help himself against a bully like Meidias. Though Demosthenes may have been physically able to stand up for himself, he could not stand alone in a court battle. By claiming a position for himself in the battle lines of justice Demosthenes asks the jury to stand beside him. Only by uniting as a hoplite force able to stand 12 (If someone whom Meidias committed hybris against should think it right to have justice and not endure in silence, he would be destroyed as an exile and in no way let off, but instead he would be seized in a desertion trial and flee from a charge of murder and be all but nailed up.) 13 120: ,

PAGE 31

31 in unity before a common enemy does the demos have the ability to save itself from men like Meidias. Through the course of this speech Demosthe nes uses accepted social conventions to construct two vastly different models. The first model is of the ideal man who embodies Athenian masculine virtue. The ideal man is a hoplite who stands with his fellow citizens, practices self restraint and mode ration, uses his abilities to uphol d the city, and submits to the laws. Of course Demosthenes nearly embodies the masculine ideal he constructs, while Meidias embodies the opposite. He is a coward, immoderate and hubristic at every turn, he abuses his abilities and possessions to dest roy smaller men, he submits to no one. A vote for conviction upholds masculine ideology, while a vote for acquittal is a vote against everything that makes an Athenian man an Athenian man.

PAGE 32

32 CHAPTER 3 AESCHINES ORATION AGAINST TIMARCHOS While Demosthenes 21 dem onstrates what happ ened to men who allowed their masculinity to rage out of control, Aeschines 1 shows masculinity gone soft. After examining the background of the speech I will turn to the text to analyze how Aeschines portrays Timarchos as mastered by his desires rather than mastering th em. Aeschines presents a multi-pronged attack on Timarchos that centers on the theme that Timarc hos did not have the self-control necessary to be a useful adviser for the city. Aeschines pr oves this point by alleging that Timarchos was a prostitute, that he squandered his patrimony, and that he then began us ing civic corruption to make the money he needed to satisfy his urges. This theme moves from the inside outward as Timarchos first devours his body, then his own po ssessions, then those of the city. Though Aeschines never calls him a kinaidos directly, that charge lurks behind each of the others he presents as he continually portrays Timarchos as a man who lacked se lf-control and sufficient masculinity. When Aeschines prosecuted Timarchos in 346/345 under a dokimasia t n rhetor n, it was in response to a public suit Timarc hos had brought against him, as he admits but he also admits that private hatreds often set right many public matters.1 He does not shy away from his true motivations: Timarchos attacked him in court, and he defends himself by prosecuting Timarchos. Their dispute arose from their service together on the embassy to Philip II of Macedon in early 346. Aeschines had been a major proponent of peace with Philip while Timarchos and his ally, Demosthenes, were less trusting of their north ern neighbor. The embassy established the Peace of Philocrates, but when the ambassadors retu rned, Demosthenes anti-Philip camp began 1

PAGE 33

33 prosecuting supporters of the treaty for acceptin g bribes from Philip and mishandling their responsibilities as ambassadors.2 Timarchos and Demosthenes filed charges against Aeschines for misc onduct, but they may not have expected the form his response would take. He could have launched a similar charge either against Timarchos or Demosthenes since both had been present on the embassy. Aeschines chose instead to file a dokimasia against Timarchos, alleging that he had violated the laws governing rhetors. Th ere were four types of dokimasiai .3 As an official entered office he underwent a dokimasia at which any citizen could speak against his fitness as a candidate. Young men underwent a dokimasia to decide if they were sons of citizens and fit to become full citizens themsevles. Invalids also underwent dokimasiai to decided if they should receive public aid. When applied to rhetors, the dokimasia took place not before, but af ter the citizen addressed the Ekklesia, by any Athenian who charged him with being unfit to speak. The four possible charges that Aeschines lists as grounds to disfranc hise a rhetor are first failure to perform filial duties or abuse of parents, second avoidance of required military service or cowardice in battle, third prostituting oneself, and f ourth squandering ones patrimony (28-32). These each imply a lack of self-control or concern about the customs of the city th at disqualified a citizen from addressing the Ekklesia. Aeschines 1 has been studied most because the main charge Aeschines levels against Timarchos is that he had been a prostitute. A lthough Aeschines devotes mo st of his attention to the accusation that Timarchos prostituted himself in his youth, his accusations do not stop there. He also accuses Timarchos of squandering his patrimony. Like Demosthenes 21, Aeschines 1 2 See Buckler and Cawkell for additional information on the Peace of Philocrates 3 Hansen 258-9.

PAGE 34

34 uses two separate charges to prove a single case. While Demosthenes 21 seeks to prove hybris in order to gain a conviction for impiety at a fest ival, this speech uses the charges of prostitution and squandering inheritance together to prove that Timarchos lacked the self-control necessary to be a useful adviser to the polis Aeschines builds his case aro und Timarchos chief failing as a citizen and a man: he was, to his core, immoderate and incapable of controlling himself. To prove that primary fault Aeschines describes many other failings that would seem to be thrown together haphazardly if they were not tied together by Timarchos essential flaw. Although Aeschines hints that Timarchos failed in his filial duties when he sold property where his mother wanted to be buried, the tw o charges that occupy most of the text are prostitution and wasting inheritance. The char ge of prostitution both occupies the bulk of the speech and is mentioned first; so it is the most re asonable place to begin. To be successful in his charge of prostitution, Aeschines needed to prove that Timarchus received payment, had multiple partners, and submitted to penetration.4 Obviously prostitution must involve payment, though payment could be difficult to prove because it coul d come in the form of gifts. Gifts between lovers involved in proper relations hips were common, so gifts alone could not help distinguish a proper relationship from an improper one. Pr omiscuity and passivity helped distinguish acceptable from unacceptable homosexual relationshi ps when payment was not clear. Indeed, each of these three qualifications are met in the speech. Aeschines declares his intent to discuss only the events of Timarchos life after he reached an age sufficient to understand the laws of the city as a young man.5 This passage reveals that, 4 Winkler 177. For a good discussion of the charge of prostitution in this case see also Halperin 94-98. 5 39: (The things which he did as a youth of sound mind and knowing the laws of the city, about these things I will make my accusation, and I think you shou ld pay attention to them).

PAGE 35

35 although he was old enough to know the laws, Timarchos refused to act according to selfrestraint and moderation, and it reve als that prostitution is not the primary charge. If prostitution were the issue, it would not matter whether or not Timarchos was old enough to understand the laws. The law allowed men who as boys had been fo rced into prostitution to refuse care to the guardian who had hired them out, but it did not a llow those men to act as rhetors. Aeschines passes over Timarchos alleged clients from befo re he reached an age of maturity because prostitution is not as important to his case as the lack of self -control and moderation that he alleges were central elements of Timarchos character. Prostitution was not Timarchos central fault, instead he was a deficient citizen because he could not control himself and therefore could not help guide the city. When he reached the age of majority Ti marchos moved in with a physician under the pretense of learning the trade, though in actuali ty he was selling his body to anyone he could. Aeschines alleges that in this period Timarchos was hired by citizens a nd foreigners alike, though he names none of them. These numerous encounters illustrate Timarchos promiscuity although Aeschines focuses instead on the me n, whom Timarchos lived with as a paid companion later in his life (40). The first is Misgolas, whom Aeschines describes as otherwise fine and noble, except for his in satiable sexual appetite. Misg olas paid Timarchos a sum of silver to live with him, and Timarchos accepte d without hesitation. Ae schines characterizes Misgolas as young, attractive, dis gusting, and suited to the act th at he chose to perform and Timarchos chose to endure (41). Although, for the sake of decorum, Aeschines refuses to name specific sex acts Timarchos and Misgolas performe d, he implies that Timarchos allowed himself to be the passive partner in a sexual relationship for pay. If to be a free male was synonymous

PAGE 36

36 with being dominant and active as Svenbro claims then his role as the passive and penetrated partner effectively emasculates Timarchos.6 Aeschines mentions the sum of silver Misgolas prepaid to Timarchos, but states afterwards that Timarchos did not yet need th e money because he had a large esta te left to him by his father. So, although he did not have any overwhelm ing need for money, Timarchos voluntarily committed these acts and enslaved himself to shameful pleasures. He ate fish constantly, attended extravagant dinners, gambled, and spen t his time with flute gi rls and courtesans, none of which are decent obsessions fo r a free and well born man (42).7 These obsessions, and his inability to control them, destroy Timarc hos as a useful adviser for the city. Aeschines uses an argument from silen ce to help demonstrate Timarchos faulty masculinity. Aeschines wrote out testimony for Misgolas to read before the court concerning his relationship with Timarchos. It is unlikely that Misgolas would have been willing to admit to any of Aeschines claims, but ne vertheless Aeschines calls on him to testify. Fisher (2001: 180, 183) explains that Misgolas would have had th ree options when presented with Aeschines challenge to testify: he could ha ve sworn an oath in denial of the testimony provided for him, he could have admitted to it all, or he could have de clined to do either, which could have resulted in a summons and perhaps a fine of 1000 drachmai. There is no way to be certain which option Misgolas chose, but Aeschines is prepared for each one (45-48). If Misgolas accepts his testimony, the success is obvious: a witness who admits to paying Timarchos for sex would clinch this case for Aeschines. If he declines to comment, Aesc hines claims that the jury should be amazed that Timarchos, who held the more dishonorable role in the relationship, is shameless 6 Svenbro 187-189. Also cf. Cartledge 56. 7 Cf. Davidson passim

PAGE 37

37 enough to address the people.8 Finally, if Misgolas denies the validity of the testimony he cannot, according to Aeschines, cover up the sh ameful reputation Timarchos holds for assuming a feminine role. The worst of these for Aeschine s would be a complete denial, but he has already prepared his jury for that possibility. If Misgolas denies the relationship here, it will seem to reinforce Timarchos shame and emasculation for jurors who have accepted Aeschines allegations as true, while any other action would be an unexp ected windfall for Aeschines. Aeschines denounces Timarchos as the least mode rate sort of person possible as he segues into a discussion of Timarchos relationship with his next long-term lover. If Timarchos had remained with Misgolas, he would have proven himself to be more moderate than his actual course of action demonstrates, and he would only have left himself vulnerable to the charge of having been an escort. Instead, after he left Misgolas, he found many other lovers, men whom Aeschines calls wild but does not describe in detail. Because of his behavior Timarchos should not be defined as an escort but as a prostitute. Here, Ae schines allows his pretense of decorum to break down; because he cannot talk around it any longer he comes out and says the word: Timarchos was not an escort, but a prostitute ( peporneumenos, 51-52). Of course, the filthy term that Aeschines displayed such chagrin for having to say aloud is the same one that the law he has already cited uses, and he had no qualms about saying it then (29). Aeschines is not content merely to charge Tima rchos with a crime punishable by atimia he seeks to convince the jury that Timarchos went beyond even that. If Timarchos had acted as an escort he would be disqualified to speak in public but Aeschines seeks to clarify that Timarchos was not even as 8 (If the man who performed the act is ashamed and would prefer to pay 100 drachmai to the treasury so as to avoid showing his own face to you, while the one who suffered the deed addresses the people, then wise indeed was the lawgiver who barred such disgusting people from the platform).

PAGE 38

38 moderate in his behavior as a male escort: Ti marchos was a common prostitute, a creature whose offences against proper masculinity offend the sensibilities of moderate and self-restrained Athenians like Aeschines and the jury. The charge of hybris was not given as possible grounds for a doikimasia t n rh torn, but it does help prove that Timarchos lacked the restraint and moderation an Athenian man needed. Aeschines begins this strand of his argument as he explains th e laws during the opening of his speech. According to the law if anyone commits hybris against a boy, man, or woman, free or slave, the guilty party is subject to the penal ties assigned by the court (15). In his comments on the law, Aeschines inserts his own opinion that anyone who hires a boy as a prostitute commits hybris against him. Aeschines gives his opinion here so that he can link prostitution and hybris two charges that did not have a fundamental connection. One function of this conflation is to link prostitution, which implied that the prost itute was penetrated by his client, with hybris so that stating that Timarchos allowed someone to commit hybris against him is equivalent to saying that Timarchos was the pass ive partner in the relationship. After living with Misgolas, Timarchos move d in with Pittalakos, a public slave of considerable means. The two had met at a gamb ling house and were quite compatible since they were both devoted to the same vices (54). While the jury may have been shocked earlier when Aeschines mentioned that Timarchos sold himself to foreigners, the revelation that he had even submitted his body to a slave would have been deva stating if the jury believed it. Aeschines implies that Timarchos was the passive partner by stating that he heard that Pittalakos committed such acts of hybris against Timarchos that he does not dare to repeat them. 9 The effect of 9 (And I have heard that such deeds and hybris were done by that man to the body of Timarchos that, by the Olympian Zeus, I cannot dare to say them to you).

PAGE 39

39 Timarchos passivity on his masculinity in this in stance is increased by Pittalakos low status as a slave who could not lega lly court free youths. The relationship between Timarchos and Pittal akos did not last l ong after Hegesandros returned to Athens. Timarchos moved in with Hegesandros, but Pittalakos missed him so much that he made a nuisance of himself around He gesandros house until Timarchos and his new lover went to Pittalakos home to both beat hi m and vandalize his property (56-59). Aeschines calls what they did to Pittalakos hybris (62), which is an example of faulty masculinity in itself. Pittalakos sought redress for these injustices but soon found himself in real danger when Hegesandros responded by claiming that Pittalakos belonged to him. Pittalakos could not defend himself legally against Hegesandros and his pow erful friends and let the matter drop (60-64). Of course a charge of hybris could prove problematic in the present case. If the victim were a woman, child, or slave, the most likely candidate to bring the case on his or her behalf would be his or her citi zen male guardian. Although any citizen could bring a graph hybre s on anothers behalf, there would have been little mo tivation for anyone other than the guardian to go through such trouble, especially when a loss by more than four fifths of the vote would result in partial atimia This explains why no one was willing to take up Pittalakos case. On the other hand, if the victim is an adult citizen male, he can bring the case on his own behalf. Aeschines alleges that Timarchos allowed others to commit hybris against him, but hybris requires intent to shame. If Timarchos intended to shame hims elf, whose business was it but his own? Aeschines accuses Timarchos of committing hybris against Pittalakos, but that incident involved several men, and the gravest threat to Pittalakos was not the violence he suffered, but the allegation that he belonged to Hegesandros rather than to the city (59-64). Although Athenian law allowed the possibi lity of charging a man with hybris against a slave there were no

PAGE 40

40 corresponding cases in which Timarchos had as saulted a free person. In addition Pittalakos dropped the affair himself, so it is not surprising that Aeschines does not emphasize this event more. Therefore Aeschines cannot lean on hybris as heavily in the present speech as Demosthenes did against Meidias but he can use it to underscore the low value Timarchos placed on his own dignity. Aeschines explicit statement that Timarchos committed hybris against himself is a culmination of all previous assaults on his masculinity : (185).10 Not only is Timarchos hubristic, but he sins contrary to nature in a way that, if he were female, would be acco rding to nature. This seems to be a clear reference to Timarchos capacity as a passive an d penetrated sexual object. While nature could mean proper as it does here, it did not need to take on that connotation.11 Nature could also mean ones innate inclinations, bu t that does not fit in this passa ge. Timarchos is unnatural not because he acts contrary to his own character: in fact he always acts in accordance with his personal nature. Aeschines constantly shows th at Timarchos is by nature an immoderate and unrestrained person. His actions are, however, unnatural because they defy Athenian cultural norms. This distinction is most apparent as Aeschines praises natural homosexual relationships in contrast to Timarchos relationships. As Aeschines accuses Timarchos of unnatural be havior and endorses other relationships, it becomes apparent that the key difference betw een Timarchos activities and those that were 10 Would someone not seem uneducated if he treated harshly a woman sinning according to her nature but used as an adviser the man who committed hybris against himself contrary to nature? 11 Winkler 171-209.

PAGE 41

41 accepted and encouraged in Athens was the elemen t of self-control. Aeschines claims that beauty was praised and still is, but on ly if it is mixed with self-control.12 He draws the distinction between the love for a beautiful and self-controlled youth, which is a mark of a noble soul, and the payment of a citizen for sex, which is proof of hybris .13 This statement simultaneously reiterates the value of self-contro l and Timarchos role as a passive object of hybris Aeschines claims that the laws mandate se lf-control in relationships between men and boys. The laws forbid relationships between boy s and slaves and tacitly support relationships between self-controlled men and boys (139). Aeschines make s a double point by citing this law. Self-control is the key to proper relationships, and Timarchos is de ficient in self-control. That Timarchos had a relationship with a slave de monstrates how little control he had, and how disgusting the results of hi s deficiency could be. Aeschines strengthens the cont rast between proper love and Timarchos relationships with historical and literary examples of proper love. Harmodios and Aristoge iton had the proper sort of love, and their appropriate re lationship trained them to b ecome benefactors of the city.14 Achilles and Patroklos are the first couple Aeschines mentions that demonstrate how poets 12 133: 13 137: 14 140: ,

PAGE 42

42 divide proper and self-controlled love from immoderate and hubristic love;15 though their status as lovers is never declared in the Iliad Aeschines claims that it is clear to an educated reader (142). He also cites Euripides for the link be tween self-control and pr oper love (151). Through these references to law, epic, and tragedy Ae schines delivers a clear message: the proper relationship between men is one of self-restraint, while Timarc hos life has been a string of examples of the opposite. The lack of self-control Timarchos has exhibited in his love lif e extends to the rest of his life, as well. This central characteristic both informs the other charges Aeschines brings and explains why a prostitute could not address the Ekklesia. Aesc hines asks what a man who has sold hybris against his own body would not sell.16 This is the fundamental concern behind prohibitions for rhetors against pros titution and wasteful living: if th ey are so immoderate in their private lives, how can they be trusted to run public affairs? Aeschines plays on this fear by claiming that when he finished devouring his body Timarchos devoured hi s estate, and finally the citys funds in his pursuit of pleasure. Therefore Timarchos will not become dangerous to the city because of what he might do in the futu re, but he has already harmed Athens through the things he has already done. While the charge of prostitution held prim acy both of place and space in this case, the charge of squandering patrimony seems to be much stronger. Aeschines anticipates Demosthenes line of reasoning that his argumen t that Timarchos lived as a prostitute and afterwards spent his whole inheritance was nonsensi cal (94). Aeschines responds that it is very 15 141: 16188:

PAGE 43

43 simple: Timarchos lived wantonly on Hegesandros dime until He gesandros ran out of money. By the time the cash ran out, Timarchos was no l onger attractive enough to support his lifestyle by taking on clients; so he turned to his inheritance for funds. The order of this argument cannot work. Aeschines implies that Timarchos was an unrestrained and immoderate deviant before he became a prostitute, so he became a prostitute to acquire his pleasures (95). This line of reasoning is obviously flawed because no free Athe nian male with ready money would turn to prostitution before he used up the money he already had. Of course the jury could only hear the case once, so Aeschines can treat the point quickly and move on be fore the jury has a chance to analyze his argument.17 Instead of being based on facts this speech is based on a theme: Timarchos devoured everything he could, from hi s body outwards, in pursuit of his shameful pleasures. It is only in light of this theme that charging a ma n who had money of prostituting himself makes any sense. Timarchos did not merely spend his inherita nce; he devoured it w hole and guzzled it down (95-96). Aeschines provides a rath er lengthy list of properties that Timarchos father left to him, all of which he squandered. There were houses slaves, workshops, and outstanding loans. There was enough before Timarchos used it all for fleeting pleasures that he would have been part of the liturgical class (97). Timarchos, however, was so addicted to fancy food and drink, courtesans, and gambling that he sold the propert y and the slaves for far less than they were worth. He also collected the outstanding debts on ly to send the money right back out, usually for whatever price he could get imme diately rather than the actual value of the property (95-96). Though common knowledge and gossip seem to be sufficient for a charge of prostitution to Aeschines, they apparently were not enough to prove that Timarchos wasted his paternal 17 Todd 171; Harris 117.

PAGE 44

44 property, because Aeschines produces testimony to prove these claims and challenges Timarchos to produce the slaves he still owns, if he has not so ld them all (100). Within this catalog of sold properties Aeschines mentions that he has hear d that Timarchos own mother begged him not to sell one of the houses so that sh e could be buried there, but her supplications were not enough to overcome Timarchos addictions (99). Timarchos mother could not address the court, and her guardian would likely be Timarchos himself. So ev en if this anecdote were true, it would be impossible to prove, but Aeschines includes it an yway. His motivations seem clear: he cannot prove that Timarchos neglected his parents because Timarchos inherited the estate only after his fathers death, and his mother could not testify, bu t he can plant the seed of doubt in the minds of the jury members that maybe Timarchos indeed f it three rather than only two of the charges possible for a dokimasia t n rhetor n The most damning testimony given for Timarcho s wasteful life is not from a friend of Aeschines who the jury might expect to lie, but from Timarchos own uncle Arignotos. Aeschines relates the family situation: there were three brothers, one of whom was Timarchos father Arizelos, and the other two were Ari gnotos and Eupolemos. The first to die was Eupolemos, after which Arizelos managed the oikos by himself and maintained Arignotos, who was both blind and physically weak. When Arizelos died and left the prop erty to Timarchos he ceased providing a sufficient living for his disabled uncle. Timarchos even failed to testify on his uncles behalf befo re the Boule at his dokimasia for public support so that he could receive state funds for his maintenance, though at the time Timarchos was on the Boule (101-104). Arignotos testimony is the strongest evidence in the case, but it is no t without problems. Arignotos was Timarchos uncle, which may mean that he hoped to inherit the oikos following his brothers death. Though ideally family relati onships were the most harmonious, it was rarely

PAGE 45

45 so. In practice relatives could be among the most serious threats to an oikos .18 Perhaps there was a logical reason for Timarchos treatment of Arignotos beyond his need to indulge himself at every opportunity. Even if there was a reason fo r Timarchos behavior a jury presented with a weak, elderly, blind man could hardly avoid feeli ng sympathy towards such a pathetic figure. Sympathy for Arignotos would necessarily resu lt in antipathy towards the spendthrift who neglected his uncle, and thereby his duties as an Athenian man. Athens did not have a public fund to support spen dthrifts and wastrels as it did to support the disabled, so Aeschines alleges that Timarchos gained public office to extort the money he could not live without. Timarchos served as an au ditor of officials leavi ng office, and in that capacity he accepted bribes to let bad officials off and threatened good ones with legal action in order to extort money from them (107). Th e contrast between a hopl ite who is willing to sacrifice his body for the good of the city and Ti marchos, who leeches funds from the city to support his body is perfectly clear in these sections. Timarchos offences as an auditor were only the beginning, however. Because he had spent his patrimony he had to borrow money at a high interest rate so that he could bribe his way into office at Andros.19 It was while managing affairs in that ally city that Timarchos displayed his lecherous behavior with the wives of the fr ee men in that city to an extent previously unknown.20 Aeschines declines to call as witnes ses the men Timarchos dishonored during that period rather than publicly humiliate them, though it se ems more likely that this is just another 18 Roisman 50. 19On the interest rate see Fisher 2001: 245. 20 .

PAGE 46

46 excuse to avoid producing witnesse s. Aeschines allows himself a bit of hyperbole as he claims that it was a good thing for Athens that there were no prospective buyers for Andros while Timarchos was there (108). Aeschines also relates a story from Timarchos time on the Boule in which he was accused of embezzlement. A man named Pamphilos discovered their plot and brought it before the council, saying that a man and woman were stea ling from the city. The man was Hegesandros and the woman was Timarchos. The Boule ini tially voted to expel Timarchos, but when a second vote was held they exonerated him (110112). Apparently the Boule was not voted a crown that year, no doubt, according to Aeschines, because they had acquitted Timarchos. This anecdote reveals that according to Aeschines th e whole city knew that Timarchos was wholly emasculated. In addition to the crimes already listed Aeschines mentions one known occurrence of bribery in which Timarchos admitted to accepting money and cast himself on the mercy of the court (113). Presumably such a case in which Timarchos had pled guilty would be verifiable. As fits with the character Aeschines has fashi oned for him, Timarchos did not respond to that setback with more moderate behavior, but instead went on to repeat the same sort of crime. Aeschines claims that Timarchos spoke out against a genuine citizen at the scrutiny of the citizen lists maintaining that the man was in actuality one of his freedmen. Of course this ploy was just another attempt to gain some fast cash, and it worked. Timarchos received 20 mnai to drop his case, though he had already sworn an oath that it was true (114-115). Following his discussions of Timarchos as a prostitute, a spendthr ift, and a corrupt politician Aeschines moves on to anticipate what sort s of arguments the defense will use. It is in his anticipation of Demosthenes defense tactics that we are faced with a paradox. Aeschines

PAGE 47

47 says that if one were to unwrap Demosthenes fr om the dainty clothes he wears while he writes his speeches and pass them around room the men of th e jury would be unable to tell whether they were a mans clothes or a woman s unless they had been told ahead of time. This is on account of Demosthenes womanish ways and kinaidia (131). A variation of the term reappears as Aeschines mentions an elderly Spartan leader who he says (sarcastically) would readily have permitted Timarchos or the kinaidos Demosthenes to prac tice politics (181). The paradox is that Aeschines applies the term to Demosthenes, but never once to Timarchos. We have already seen, however, that there is reason enough to assume passivity in this case from the numerous passages in whic h Aeschines attacks Timarchos through innuendo. So why does Aeschines refrai n from calling Timarchos a kinaidos ? A kinaidos was unrestrained, as Timarchos was. A kinaidos was sexually promiscuous, as Timarchos was. In short, a kinaidos was a shameful individual concerned only with fulfilling his immediate desires, a description that applies to Timarchos just as easily as Demosthenes according to Aeschines account of his life. Aeschines frequently denoun ces Timarchos vices, but those vices are his addiction to food, drink, gambling, and often courte sans. Aeschines implies that Timarchos may have enjoyed his role with his clients by stati ng that he did not hesitate to accommodate them, but he never says directly that he enjoyed it (42). I would propose that Aeschines does not allege that Timarchos was a kinaidos because that would have implied clearly that he enjoyed his role with his clients, and if he enj oyed that role they may not have been clients at all but men who had their way with Timarchos for free. That role would be as shameful as that of a prostitute, but it was not actionable under a dokimasia While the most noteworthy charge in this spe ech is that of prostitution, Aeschines did not win on that allegation alone. Th is case was convincing not becau se of a single outstanding and

PAGE 48

48 salacious charge, but because of Timarchos numerous failings that Aeschines presents. Aeschines does not attempt to prove Timarchos had prostituted himself, he instead succeeded in proving, at least to the jurys satisfaction, the theme that Ti marchos began with devouring himself, then moved on to his patrimony, and finally to the city itself. The picture of Timarchos as an unrestrained deviant is powerful because of the links between prostitution, wasteful spending, and corruption as a city official. Pe rhaps none of these charges would have been powerful enough alone to gain a conviction, especial ly without any witnesses for the prostitution charge. Together, however, these charges make Timarchos as faulty in his masculinity as Meidias was. Although his masculinity was not strong enough while Meidias was overpowering, Timarchos is a dange r to the city nonetheless.

PAGE 49

49 CHAPTER 4 CONCLUSION In his discussion of violence, Herm an conclude s that the official forces responsible for perpetuating the democracy were not strong enou gh to maintain law and order. Instead, the Athenians relied upon citizen hoplites, legitimat e self-help, and the internalization of suprapersonal values. In Hermans opinion, th e most important factor in maintaining the democracy was the tacit backing of the hoplite cla ss. He admittedly draws this conclusion not from any primary source evidence, but because he cannot see how the democratic system functioned if the citizen hoplite army were not the power behind the scenes.1 I think Herman has underestimated the democracy in Athens by placing it in the hands of the hoplites rather than the whole demos .2 On the one hand, of the 30,000 or so Athenian citizens, only 7,000-8,000 were hoplites (Ober 1989: 129). On the other, Herman assumes that there must have been a coercive force to uphold the democracy, but according to the discursive paradigm internalized suprapersonal values shou ld have been enough to hold the city together under normal circumstances. In extraordinary circumstances, the city could unite under the Boule and prosecute serious threats more efficiently, as it did when the herms were mutilated.3 For less serious threats to the city, like the thre ats that Meidias and Timarchos may have posed, ordinary prosecution was sufficient to define the bounds of acceptable activity. Demosthenes 21 illustrates how excessive masc uline energies could be used against a defendant in court. Demosthenes seeks to show that Meidias is not only a menace to private citizens, but to the whole state. He proves his case by beginning with the offences he suffered 1 Herman 1994: 115. 2 Cf. Cartledge for the importance of the thetes in the democracy. 3 Hunter 120.

PAGE 50

50 himself, but quickly progresses in to a discussion of how Meidias has harmed the city. Perhaps the most damning characteristic Demosthenes disc usses is Meidias lack of concern for how the demos views him. A man so preoccupied with his ow n personal agendas and gratification that he disregards the collective will of the city is dangerous and must be censured. Timarchos usefulness was also limited because he put his interests ahead of the citys, but for the opposite reason. While hybris was an excess of masculine energies, Aeschines accuses Timarchos of playing a womans role. The most in teresting charge in this speech is prostitution, but Aeschines also attacks Timarchos as a son an d a citizen. Timarchos robbed the city to fund his own extravagance, while Meidias shamed othe r citizens to amuse himself. These two men suffer from opposite faults, too much and too little manliness, but the result for each is the same: imbalances in masculinity do not harm onl y the imbalanced individual, but the whole community. Through Demosthenes 21 and Aeschines 1 we have seen how masculine values can be manipulated toward two opposite extremes and app lied to political enemies. Because there was the constant danger of prosecution under a myriad of charges, these masculine ideals were more than guidelines to the rhetors w ho guided public policy. While a non-elite citizen could probably do as he pleased in his private life, citizens who held highly visible posts, such as ambassadors, would have had to be considerably more caref ul about how their actions could be perceived. If one of these visible targets allowed his ma sculinity and pride to become too powerful he could end up facing a case much like the one Meid ias did. Perhaps it would not be a charge of hybris but as Demosthenes 21 proves, even if hybris were not the technical charge it could still appear as frequently as if it were. Likewise in the case of Aeschines 1, if a man did not appear to hold his masculine honor in high enough regard he could face charges arising from his deficient

PAGE 51

51 masculinity. Indeed, if we accept that masculinity was a spectrum with kinaidic behavior on one end and hubristic behavior on the other, these two cases show well bot h the range of proper masculinity, and that the key featur e that defined the spectrum of masculinity was self-control.

PAGE 52

52 LIST OF REFERENCES Buckler, J. 2000. Demosthenes and Aeschines. In I. W orthington, ed., Demosthenes: Statesman and Orator New York. 114-158. Cairns, D. 1996. Hybris, Dishonour, and Thinking Big. JHS 116: 1-32. Cartledge, P. 1998. The Machismo of the Athenian Empire or the Reign of the Phaulus ? In L. Foxhall and J. Salmon, eds., When Men Were Men: Mascu linity, Power and Identity in Classical Antiquity London. 54-67. Cawkwell, G. 1963a. Demosthenes Polic y after the Peace of Philocrates I. CQ 13.1: 120128. ----------------. 1963b. Dem osthenes Policy after the Peace of Philocrates II. CQ 13.2: 200213. Cohen, D. 1995. Law, Violence and Community in Classical Athens Cambridge. Cohen, E. 2002. An Unprofitabl e Masculinity. In P. Cartledge, E. Cohen, and L. Foxhall, eds., Money, Labour, and Land: Approaches to the Economies of Ancient Greece London. 100-112. Davidson, J. 1997. Courtesans & Fishcakes: The Consum ing Passions of Classical Athens New York. Fisher, N.R.E. 1992. Hybris: A Study in the Values of Honour and Shame in Ancient Greece Warminster U.K. ----------------. 1998. Violence, Masculinity, and the Law in Classical Athens. In L. Foxhall and J. Salmon, eds., When Men Were Men: Masculinity Power and Identity in Classical Antiquity London. 68-97. ----------------, ed. 2001. Aeschines Against Timarchos Oxford. Halperin, D. 1990. One Hundred Years of Homosexuality: and Other Essays on Greek Love New York. Hansen, M. 1999. The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes Norman, Oklahoma. Harris, E. 1989. Demosthenes Speech against Meidias. HSCP 92: 117-136. Herman, G. 1993. Tribal and Civic C odes of Behaviour in Lysias I. CQ 43.2: 406-419.

PAGE 53

53 ----------------. 1994. H ow Violent Was Athenian Society? In R. Osborne and S. Hornblower, eds., Ritual, Finance, Politics: Athenian Democr atic Accounts presented to David Lewis. Oxford. 99-117. ----------------. 2006. Morality and Behavior in Democra tic Athens: a Social History Cambridge. Hunter, V. 1993. Policing Athens: Social Control in the Attic Lawsuits, 420-320 B.C. Princeton. MacDowell, D. 1976. Hybris in Athens. G&R 23.1: 14-31. ----------------, ed. 1990. Demosthenes Against Meidias London. Morris, I. 2000. Archaeology as Cultural History: Words and Things in Iron Age Greece Malden, Massachusetts. Ober, J. 1989. Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens Princeton. ----------------. 1994. P ower and Oratory in Democratic Athens. In I. Worthington, ed., Persuasion: Greek Rhetoric in Action London. 85-108. Roisman, J. 2005. The Rhetoric of Manhood: Mascul inity in the Attic Orators Berkeley. Svenbro, J. 1988. Phrasikleia: An Anthropology of Reading in Ancient Greece. Ithaca. Todd, S. The Use and Abuse of the Attic Orators. G&R 37.2: 159-178. Winkler, J.J. 1990. Laying Down the Law: Th e Oversight of Mens Sexual Behavior in Classical Athens. In D. Halperi n, J.J. Winkler, and F. Zeitlin, eds., Before Sexuality: The Construction of Erotic Experience in the Ancient Greek World Princeton. 171-209.

PAGE 54

BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH Seth Boutin was born in Shreveport, Loui siana, in 1983. Aft er being homeschooled through middle school Seth attended Caddo Magne t High School, where he captained their nationally ranked quiz team. After high school Seth went to Baylor University in Waco, Texas. While at Baylor Seth majored in University Scho lars with a focus in classics. Upon graduating from Baylor, Seth began his studie s at the University of Florida. Seth plans to continue his education by working toward his doctoral degree.


xml version 1.0 encoding UTF-8
REPORT xmlns http:www.fcla.edudlsmddaitss xmlns:xsi http:www.w3.org2001XMLSchema-instance xsi:schemaLocation http:www.fcla.edudlsmddaitssdaitssReport.xsd
INGEST IEID E20101203_AAAACI INGEST_TIME 2010-12-03T16:23:39Z PACKAGE UFE0022264_00001
AGREEMENT_INFO ACCOUNT UF PROJECT UFDC
FILES
FILE SIZE 34002 DFID F20101203_AABBLV ORIGIN DEPOSITOR PATH boutin_s_Page_35.QC.jpg GLOBAL false PRESERVATION BIT MESSAGE_DIGEST ALGORITHM MD5
5fe1880f698271631233b5239b3590b2
SHA-1
0cba5b5fd8b16c3ab7a16f66359fa71958f4e96e
109318 F20101203_AABBEA boutin_s_Page_17.jpg
1291341420643c39807c8c4d35ded9dd
d743a6ee7e42c1baf2ce065a41c7ee28a1cf1424
1051971 F20101203_AABBGY boutin_s_Page_42.jp2
6af839d815b97329ffb570fc04f954b9
f12325c640a56fce943c8c9908c3ff46c883b120
8736 F20101203_AABBLW boutin_s_Page_35thm.jpg
094ebc1b5e94d9cca9906eab37bb593a
e8594bb7f45275d273612bb9087b6339774c8ed1
112124 F20101203_AABBEB boutin_s_Page_18.jpg
0647baf08f10df4f24a32e217df77732
4f53af73f51c0470e639057ddad2c36a86b2b61b
1051950 F20101203_AABBGZ boutin_s_Page_43.jp2
561147274ea9b7815ffcde052addfa68
3c1dd2f847da6086cfc139b56295305c23ce1d5a
33957 F20101203_AABBLX boutin_s_Page_36.QC.jpg
5a42207d0c36f4cafd173f853711d1d9
dfb4751e8d1f6cf1ac78aedbce3bee26d6d933a1
108913 F20101203_AABBEC boutin_s_Page_19.jpg
97750ddc9c4b55fe109a1b4b254f161d
0d8c6b5c8c72e8a7c1d3524e4f0a693920f24232
8410 F20101203_AABBLY boutin_s_Page_36thm.jpg
ddf4f73c792c3e2a557caa2877e91535
8b8887730d0668d8b622303580f69e5fa39c1260
109386 F20101203_AABBED boutin_s_Page_20.jpg
bb2ad030720354ff825d5fd8b56323bc
ae83b0be19501bff31f8da3578b461e2339219f2
25271604 F20101203_AABBJA boutin_s_Page_46.tif
50106e654c7e32fb233ad6421a443c8e
f18768969dec59d34ac3da2183adce7024dbff90
39018 F20101203_AABBLZ boutin_s_Page_37.QC.jpg
7960644815d101ee18723167a4ede8c3
9c98ab5f9eb9bbcff4fec39e69a7c5cf3e88cca7
106822 F20101203_AABBEE boutin_s_Page_21.jpg
203e53f19c72f299fcdfc9fbc87f5731
c584ba29ed3266cb34af1c417c9895d8fc41540b
F20101203_AABBJB boutin_s_Page_47.tif
855ce6e491eee1767176f5a2b90daaba
2d56abbb72c313104c60a53b9e492063ee9e9c23
99875 F20101203_AABBEF boutin_s_Page_22.jpg
416ae18cab51d7c14f22de86c5c0e5f9
998fb1fc3d918486a22189e232022007337b8356
F20101203_AABBJC boutin_s_Page_49.tif
f8a87059e1e47379a9e1569137a09032
2078442a45288f24fb46cd36da9f0b4fc35509c1
109605 F20101203_AABBEG boutin_s_Page_23.jpg
5f34db8d75bbc626336011701c95e581
a49e2886dc8da926af1caa2393bfe1cb910addf3
F20101203_AABBJD boutin_s_Page_50.tif
88c8653113948828f51a2faf7e38993e
f0ddc5d9ff2da7919ac920d2fbc25d871416956d
105814 F20101203_AABBEH boutin_s_Page_24.jpg
71b4246398a46987534578bdf8b69c52
b45a98c63acc8a418836179751211145de70aaa4
F20101203_AABBJE boutin_s_Page_51.tif
3e6a92583857e1a82da02b9b0532de7a
9ec30542e191791fd33df51a1715883fe9a42041
111584 F20101203_AABBEI boutin_s_Page_25.jpg
bb111eb63fae8701d93d9caf4a4036d4
f6accd06080c2bb019640e8d7bb479cd5b7e0317
F20101203_AABBJF boutin_s_Page_52.tif
32ad6f3ed31918d5628ca8eba33db913
6b89a254f47cb73e0bd268032a01442468349dd7
100911 F20101203_AABBEJ boutin_s_Page_26.jpg
eae33734e9c5dfe15148737a3361e290
42273c5d7219d7f9c2559300bc1644bb4e689be8
F20101203_AABBJG boutin_s_Page_53.tif
29206280d04b5cb1e357a4ea84460a51
34f66831a1c17e765613cf88377bf469a9e983ee
107252 F20101203_AABBEK boutin_s_Page_27.jpg
aeeee40ffc83afc0ab0305d1b576fda0
cd1e5edc513ccb1117bd8f7b39127ce74447ac1f
F20101203_AABBJH boutin_s_Page_54.tif
2c06c176d5d19ef1c06ca93cffabccc6
a973f9568b3ccac638932bf4bc5b04ca0951fec9
108366 F20101203_AABBEL boutin_s_Page_28.jpg
c312364b7d286b6473b9409ab6ae3af8
fd5e41de30f078f509f8ae46ec2bf31fe40f5c58
1973 F20101203_AABBJI boutin_s_Page_01thm.jpg
e624d7e42ea71255f2fe454da9166bc2
50b5fb9756aa1770281845633b946423030e9d42
268042 F20101203_AABBJJ boutin_s.pdf
bc422927359b5d6774c8c4d938f8afb9
821bd35a561393dafd5bff24a0093aba4903a627
112999 F20101203_AABBEM boutin_s_Page_29.jpg
09efb73c7da34a7b2c881aaada560095
fda45c868e25f4aa773922c2eda85ecc8e967275
7412 F20101203_AABBJK boutin_s_Page_01.QC.jpg
e2c5267788d93c6b9b27b94e845d3e9a
1cc292a544116ec40d26c20473522dbbdfab494f
115012 F20101203_AABBEN boutin_s_Page_30.jpg
2359ccf043e1d79f519e0e40dd4daf75
2c3427496927469fb519a06ea5efea17e0f2a900
1098 F20101203_AABBJL boutin_s_Page_02.QC.jpg
ed9fde72f7d3f266c7150886d2b5662a
b46c12573dd8455d568e86b250235a60a34fbc26
497 F20101203_AABBJM boutin_s_Page_02thm.jpg
f45f7d1ea42acea8f56c024dff48ab64
b2cc4050a852068095ee3080bbf731ad020904b9
49061 F20101203_AABBEO boutin_s_Page_31.jpg
3ff4b06c164332b11db96095df867db4
e5f1395295fac762c2e20aec78bc7a5157e1fd0d
1444 F20101203_AABBJN boutin_s_Page_03.QC.jpg
18051965e7b51a3581ebecd3397ec994
d5eea9ba7e94df4c332690aa4a98e63e4ca843bf
103799 F20101203_AABBEP boutin_s_Page_32.jpg
e8d42985558dfb9ec7df2814ee3efdfc
bf8913818a4d1a15cdce90a7d9e20fcf99be7753
10943 F20101203_AABBJO boutin_s_Page_04.QC.jpg
2b52290a3df46b75b7dbdd9ad67fc3ab
04fbb83539cebd3c67d2bd509f2b6e8093892115
102978 F20101203_AABBEQ boutin_s_Page_33.jpg
9ef51543558aca2877effbe90d171e95
b7c10cf6bc71e9c6125b12f43a989e2f982d4cbf
2729 F20101203_AABBJP boutin_s_Page_04thm.jpg
4223a7bd36b3f89a0c0d2c2e30e67a5e
db70b8fcf16c7a2486d8ac3975c49efea8fd8536
117513 F20101203_AABBER boutin_s_Page_34.jpg
e9d41aff9ecf3a3be10b57f58143eded
4943bdf114f06e18a25b8e6719b0c312aa3dcd56
11688 F20101203_AABBJQ boutin_s_Page_05.QC.jpg
9c4aa27a32d533fcbf0fc104ead60145
06610432c20788145fba21ec06d5ca2cc34d48b5
105640 F20101203_AABBES boutin_s_Page_35.jpg
08c0e925ac0d7841c4d8d73242485b9b
faa6c5eac5e8aaa52784e8991ac4b4eaadc3e355
104657 F20101203_AABBET boutin_s_Page_36.jpg
4793a1046be319c5419156d332040753
3048a1a7de2e8b562af3a07f90875596ed9d4762
3121 F20101203_AABBJR boutin_s_Page_05thm.jpg
e6d1ff889bb6e8c9fc75d4f44ab16261
e0332c8e48c12fa0c904265dea0b7b82dd918144
120806 F20101203_AABBEU boutin_s_Page_37.jpg
33e374c0b459603bd7834dfc95dfefee
3959f700a9beb78d9cf7d9711c639cfb66489534
3931 F20101203_AABBJS boutin_s_Page_06.QC.jpg
36da5d33fdececc8495ded2becbccaf2
67ed637a89747ecca7f0251bbf4c98eab3682124
112055 F20101203_AABBEV boutin_s_Page_39.jpg
3a525584a5ac4c7ac3f92ec08e7b82fd
b04abb371fcd1cbc667e4dd0c5b3deb8e1b1a416
7733 F20101203_AABBJT boutin_s_Page_07thm.jpg
d2dc940e068b9f6d4020313d13ecf5fd
7a7383a9a67835331aaf4d9ef879608eedfb51b8
102691 F20101203_AABBEW boutin_s_Page_40.jpg
c84762321ddadb1a1e734f5b1f81a3d4
b4433831931f4f55b2c79c4739294d7ebbd5ed6f
5715 F20101203_AABBJU boutin_s_Page_08.QC.jpg
ef19e813570074f2bee8faa5d48a7a64
f6294c603adfd0e23745cb0b26f6b2aadd20f446
103007 F20101203_AABBEX boutin_s_Page_42.jpg
e653b6ebabf8d6aba3300581682eaf8a
c16e2f87e765e578f43ff817e8ad54fb0cd7969f
1527 F20101203_AABBJV boutin_s_Page_08thm.jpg
89dc3380f7058ce082897b5646f2fa51
38fd4fc2894e6edf08635fc3561ef25b401321ea
109212 F20101203_AABBEY boutin_s_Page_43.jpg
acb464c09b4fa14aa48d715157c4cb02
8d4735d68db32386939ec73cf4af01cfe8a5de49
33952 F20101203_AABBJW boutin_s_Page_09.QC.jpg
8bd1f3046c1588f8039aeea5632a5056
06b2cbb2b786bb031bef73495d61f68d77d2ba8f
112170 F20101203_AABBEZ boutin_s_Page_44.jpg
7c0b02d235f964101cc44bf1101ef471
fe05e0950a9972f32b98a2bc73ebe229eea82165
8346 F20101203_AABBJX boutin_s_Page_09thm.jpg
ff353ffe3681dd11647aca78423e65b2
f3e6cd1ce2bd56b3712f663795454f7297b763c1
1051967 F20101203_AABBHA boutin_s_Page_44.jp2
b6f8e9aa3daa351b84180b5929926f33
1d579658553c666b79ebf8e1bc10e7c73b6c20c9
34814 F20101203_AABBJY boutin_s_Page_10.QC.jpg
417c2fe6e8fef23454e637949f0783fc
a38b07c52ca94e587c78d6b0b30eb0f5e7a532e3
1051979 F20101203_AABBHB boutin_s_Page_45.jp2
04282aa5f8dd7dd4748fa81503ef9aa6
17000340ca39e988528eae57271fc9f870ca6568
8674 F20101203_AABBJZ boutin_s_Page_10thm.jpg
3c442a15bdb34ab369d3341c6b439e1f
d95db9b7b678a79ddce88a453f1493aef8131b43
1051952 F20101203_AABBHC boutin_s_Page_46.jp2
8a476f06ef637f4c88a97488135bc1da
11152f715a3471280a5292bb596884ecb4b52206
1051939 F20101203_AABBHD boutin_s_Page_47.jp2
8d538d4aaf382943925680a750f90384
f8eece5750d7939c1a608395bfea41ee45fb1f19
9259 F20101203_AABBMA boutin_s_Page_37thm.jpg
c05acea74e726d63c3d261aa4a426c44
714ba2326687605a7fa79377a908c904ec42fc97
1051941 F20101203_AABBHE boutin_s_Page_49.jp2
c5e04103a4eed16278cddb7e0fedd4a9
f880e65ccde03ee916b2e804006b669aa5d95943
37032 F20101203_AABBMB boutin_s_Page_38.QC.jpg
b37d40136987045af87cb4ce35e8ec73
a7803e63502ff28d2724c35ffd9fabea1b320590
1051909 F20101203_AABBHF boutin_s_Page_50.jp2
9e10ca467fa5e95c424bbdb9b7bb81f2
9f9faff07bbc9a0a3cea825c0f1f2dfe70792ffd
9091 F20101203_AABBMC boutin_s_Page_38thm.jpg
ad8777e28c830cdfb58ec91832d7b84c
60931627426313d9c1d56e6bd6a4151ca9281f20
176842 F20101203_AABBHG boutin_s_Page_51.jp2
5101654e34493fde910aa1d25699252c
6b384447a286e895ae2b89823575dbefec9b3dde
36082 F20101203_AABBMD boutin_s_Page_39.QC.jpg
dab078f275cff87abda573bf36cfe6c6
de86623e733949641b9ab68cf525426230d88af3
1048788 F20101203_AABBHH boutin_s_Page_52.jp2
4126be39c901f67d2e663cd28df22a0b
6673a8cbcb299c9b315e547e34e7f270c1b0d325
9144 F20101203_AABBME boutin_s_Page_39thm.jpg
47ba2567fd17b4d828f75710547c4b32
bb9c4b38798aa29ec87a7dd009ab22d38f870099
799440 F20101203_AABBHI boutin_s_Page_53.jp2
9c9d3a8bf1748113825ff802e76e5171
8a3c6e7887b122b9559f9e985736597dcc43ee27
34998 F20101203_AABBMF boutin_s_Page_40.QC.jpg
ff17b77522873c160fc272bded4d5b62
dda0b47ea50e06b2bf63cf2707937ec94ff67959
329164 F20101203_AABBHJ boutin_s_Page_54.jp2
6680431fb7f0ed870ad74ddc63cc54c0
6936d76b2df9728f7f8447ab67d011c7b3d05a50
8428 F20101203_AABBMG boutin_s_Page_40thm.jpg
4d84266f4d12c656a0df21f2be6e1d39
adf7ee24e2b6bf7af588cbda6cda66b7502668f7
F20101203_AABBHK boutin_s_Page_01.tif
6348094a5df827e9d8492287c836630a
e8663d07482ece3e2ed6902298e9ecd1ebb9c508
30881 F20101203_AABBMH boutin_s_Page_41.QC.jpg
1acc89ce9b8726416c8b8c265a4d5a5c
2e7cb4b11a7db47b85e64a7cff7440a258816f80
7673 F20101203_AABBMI boutin_s_Page_41thm.jpg
e5ff51f7fa36d0d892060b5bc9d9c983
1cde10c3982b85431e6aa0ddc0464a3a7d36b61b
F20101203_AABBHL boutin_s_Page_02.tif
d2800f82359099dbd2ad3f57838c7493
6d11cf65f386a8934b46f4bffb10cc0dbc92eab6
33432 F20101203_AABBMJ boutin_s_Page_42.QC.jpg
70da301cfba67f72642448aa1f554355
04d94934d5786d21fdd984bb995c92d3ef25cd8b
F20101203_AABBHM boutin_s_Page_03.tif
93d2b79a37b115813abb9a960bab64b1
498b2c1044e9e648cbb52b59a39de2fca68d0a77
8320 F20101203_AABBMK boutin_s_Page_42thm.jpg
bf3472d4e87857c364aa6532fa7e1872
067f7351b04b38946532e11ff40f84c474bd7cb1
F20101203_AABBHN boutin_s_Page_04.tif
909ba6d4f77734408316b53afc449ad7
71b9ba64eae8a4148fc2ddedf6d1dd26e219db94
35544 F20101203_AABBML boutin_s_Page_43.QC.jpg
2f811bca8bb4f83e563d9b0c389ccdd1
a148a451fab4642323ba4e0e141bbd1d85f9b3c3
F20101203_AABBHO boutin_s_Page_05.tif
2b5214d710926e44f3e06b846267f5ee
d8acc39256d4acdeb44698e6cf5463d4cf8b4f19
8780 F20101203_AABBMM boutin_s_Page_43thm.jpg
80aa73437d495b085cc632b8d0c07207
9e066689ead6198cb252237ade42f70824767dbe
36225 F20101203_AABBMN boutin_s_Page_44.QC.jpg
478ae0c25553b71bfbaa1b63c9f890a9
e758c0fcbf3345d26bcbefdc3eda68525eaa2044
F20101203_AABBHP boutin_s_Page_06.tif
aba2f26354ea28f26bc361c92422f05b
8eb7852f6e337b9ff2817fc4944b675018b8e9a2
33671 F20101203_AABBMO boutin_s_Page_45.QC.jpg
b136d3102172b13fc561e73d72ddc9b7
0df1962bf65d2e6b74d073a5f5ab126a098b6378
F20101203_AABBHQ boutin_s_Page_07.tif
b5c02d554e294458ab49071811bca8e4
d69391f4edbf0af54cfdcdf82cae15a3b342a421
95894 F20101203_AABBCU boutin_s_Page_41.jpg
1a6e58163b72b1f2cdab380a8e57a2de
04623f167af9edf0eaa5ad9e9d7e289e7e66c9e9
8215 F20101203_AABBMP boutin_s_Page_45thm.jpg
62e8a698e5aad5238ef2ddec74029dbd
e2b4f7a5e01bac8a9eb0d818b68a1cea0e2c83be
F20101203_AABBHR boutin_s_Page_09.tif
dfbc7ed03de56228b69dc6542088d75c
31b626116891acc71320b741768702b2af47eb4a
F20101203_AABBCV boutin_s_Page_12.tif
5faaa7e82f529af1cc57b28503bab3b0
4ba5a0db2115c05414541f02ea605fd18070aa6a
34029 F20101203_AABBMQ boutin_s_Page_46.QC.jpg
286d52686bc25656e13a9769c8d75cc1
5fb3e213a302d95cea20fc0233ab35a25f6ad306
F20101203_AABBHS boutin_s_Page_10.tif
b25b1b59919913d06ad3e0790cc211f2
bb2cebcbc798e4c2d562af8ff397c1d172af058c
F20101203_AABBCW boutin_s_Page_08.tif
1b4b634bc2480d1c62df6ccafb4808c8
2dbb263bb4af70784d3eaecbb2837626073b603b
8985 F20101203_AABBMR boutin_s_Page_46thm.jpg
a0c7c67c9a41c33d0d5d44afc87153c4
3661ed31dcf69d09e4b1e65d5d777fbe0a360c5e
F20101203_AABBHT boutin_s_Page_11.tif
0ef9bef22362722e134ff31c19de6ef9
7658e3637f0ebcca363d7d85868fee0686382dd3
8667 F20101203_AABBCX boutin_s_Page_20thm.jpg
250724cf05c331ce94a3c72cbc3fdf8b
42af47ca5446dfa93b1bd09f1224cb1e8da2ddb8
36095 F20101203_AABBMS boutin_s_Page_47.QC.jpg
c1472a3c519b76b5e5923ddd3c73b452
6311c82d7ba4de11347cc2129404fb42231e0c5b
F20101203_AABBHU boutin_s_Page_13.tif
1ed2c408240ca6a3e25a048fc0e9b1d6
7a2a70d5df9b37538aad4a7101f728c81608ed0c
621 F20101203_AABBCY boutin_s_Page_03thm.jpg
e2f2f459af67b5be16cc64e72bb76f8b
e42747145d24b88d63e136a6557870314621c22a
8966 F20101203_AABBMT boutin_s_Page_47thm.jpg
b8df4ac8e851db95f1ec9676692df4e5
a0b1b8e877c109ca2509857124939dda22034769
F20101203_AABBHV boutin_s_Page_14.tif
cf6f4a02dcabe45b24b5bdf52d2c3c9d
42ee00eac1dfbfde608bd8c089701c08ecd827dd
1275 F20101203_AABBCZ boutin_s_Page_06thm.jpg
daf99bf6556f4b9eb5841d0bb43b11b7
2eb9e0c10c8f902b6127da596143118eb1bca0bf
F20101203_AABBHW boutin_s_Page_15.tif
86ac3b83b50821e74c7f2369682adbdf
bdd00bf3c58d0f5307a61ad630fc7c4e4e9a5e1b
16512 F20101203_AABBMU boutin_s_Page_48.QC.jpg
42a7e0c32cdc5deb41908e036c4455cd
348f00a55f8c76df41f3be6d6ae4dd2da553ff09
F20101203_AABBHX boutin_s_Page_16.tif
6306b3904ea3342dce76d42472cf14c4
f88281858f2a9b0582eda9786a1ed890f415b516
4270 F20101203_AABBMV boutin_s_Page_48thm.jpg
2f6647bbfc895e93e4acb7d070b64459
b2f56002636559d7566ec5257dd7424e477958a6
100956 F20101203_AABBFA boutin_s_Page_45.jpg
d186e20072bae0b13942c5868f09c3e9
721257ac495723ad635130bbbe6132f1e2f049b9
F20101203_AABBHY boutin_s_Page_17.tif
e903d54be97d0fd077028937d4df71ca
db495f4f784e21107358b0726e773dcf127e63c2
31460 F20101203_AABBMW boutin_s_Page_49.QC.jpg
dd155109b26c1010ea0fbadd4dc79c74
35e1fb18c809ed435342ba5063c6c1dbd21b2dd8
104885 F20101203_AABBFB boutin_s_Page_46.jpg
2df2be16291173f3831b529adbafd611
a08436af2483fb21479168fa52bc969a7fc9b8cd
F20101203_AABBHZ boutin_s_Page_18.tif
3883cf33c712d09a4c73428cf8b3fc1f
c4e53b7fb376106569aed37d1e2595292290c177
7807 F20101203_AABBMX boutin_s_Page_49thm.jpg
2824441ae3c32360a03ee2aa518c3c30
3514b3ba4439bd3171640cbd9b5cf80f2745875d
110460 F20101203_AABBFC boutin_s_Page_47.jpg
6b52d5f72bd445c11de27afb01fa09e4
95bdd7116dee4cb7a7d5c52d38cf787a08609440
37210 F20101203_AABBKA boutin_s_Page_11.QC.jpg
6d95aff0d1ca7af5671feaae6dc63c76
30aa9c05a310483ed2c9b7ba0808988f446ebc93
36434 F20101203_AABBMY boutin_s_Page_50.QC.jpg
5d824a12d9570c74748e604aa748140b
addd11cd422afbae7430729f7973fa6d8be44c9a
50016 F20101203_AABBFD boutin_s_Page_48.jpg
d9ee26991571f9a1b45dde5c63e4f3a0
389259dee7fe8c23b7b195859ba8be72968a601b
9204 F20101203_AABBKB boutin_s_Page_11thm.jpg
4c4dae997b737f09c79f11331596225e
71163ccb41072ce3d84f3c96f5e4dacefe325b03
9136 F20101203_AABBMZ boutin_s_Page_50thm.jpg
813e739d681d174a3ad0954dedeb410d
48e99561a9e59c9ef8d4624903ff0b41e2248de6
98903 F20101203_AABBFE boutin_s_Page_49.jpg
ee4d520710c2ac98c6aee1fdf90e533a
4e232471dbc7c02f23770631fa77291cec44e436
31105 F20101203_AABBKC boutin_s_Page_12.QC.jpg
75f0adfe44dc711c47bd28d76357f4f5
6867afd90b02da4cbb382688fef05193f4d423a4
111296 F20101203_AABBFF boutin_s_Page_50.jpg
645ddf5457bd156771a701632e02e903
e7478c611fb9435dbdf25bc4af24cd626e73ee11
7732 F20101203_AABBKD boutin_s_Page_12thm.jpg
9dfe55c7307146caf3d4b9088dd69ed6
030982823331f2e3bbc92f71941127dc76868884
18284 F20101203_AABBFG boutin_s_Page_51.jpg
5c4efe884698c8115c8169778049888d
3db1a50c4003370996da018176a5e829a36f9879
33179 F20101203_AABBKE boutin_s_Page_13.QC.jpg
76605a6454961a6d495f144a8ff871f1
1a9e740e1d5b62cff2fa3a06790bce8eee6342ef
95303 F20101203_AABBFH boutin_s_Page_52.jpg
34965904264fe8168786e589ead6fd82
649fcb4724e95c11d05878a097b8624e90a4df9d
8523 F20101203_AABBKF boutin_s_Page_13thm.jpg
f2e7f8ec19aa1b600ead819e568dafe6
9426e4fc57742373a72eab2a12925847b78faf6e
71651 F20101203_AABBFI boutin_s_Page_53.jpg
7e5f063d2e387d42a1541e52c422bb74
448bf14b5c2008c383bf0845faf57e9ab746f757
30647 F20101203_AABBKG boutin_s_Page_14.QC.jpg
515085b3bef4828f5540289cc8dbfd95
8ca24423966ff828f41aa643ea4325ba43edbb34
32886 F20101203_AABBFJ boutin_s_Page_54.jpg
53bf9eae91fcc2ce462655db51353e4a
518e0e8490be57156242ededc3b460c45d9092bc
216624 F20101203_AABBFK boutin_s_Page_01.jp2
6b340bce31288530b276bf4d3e12e2fd
f452eea27e0532f5824369c6d0886fec75474882
7756 F20101203_AABBKH boutin_s_Page_14thm.jpg
5ae7faaa446f82e3fcd3d03e7b516db2
45c47457578297e6e2a672370deb6c4ef5509db9
22736 F20101203_AABBFL boutin_s_Page_02.jp2
b337c3bcb2cb27f7f1c9f4ff55e4027c
84b5c3a78bfa32061f012834dc5e15eed16cb409
34336 F20101203_AABBKI boutin_s_Page_15.QC.jpg
33a6b6be30390c47f0a24d875663777b
1cb090b0de95ce1e68c8d9d8e4a47a04d9941f35
37199 F20101203_AABBFM boutin_s_Page_03.jp2
2f5a02bdcb3ad37c52689270431cb337
fb2ad6c70ac5f89b9570da98f7869bfd78d0d30b
8732 F20101203_AABBKJ boutin_s_Page_15thm.jpg
afebb119d366620a350ccc95bc0d21a5
57e28166f074aacb4b1c3de463a16c9e18f5ce5a
26933 F20101203_AABBKK boutin_s_Page_16.QC.jpg
cf602d4d80cd271ce5b677b3951056e6
e27632745d74c547add4625cb9b9206f24faadba
336024 F20101203_AABBFN boutin_s_Page_04.jp2
94f9f0ecd9eb3611fc86547d09f486c7
4591930803da145e7c9d54546cc0914bbd593c5b
6936 F20101203_AABBKL boutin_s_Page_16thm.jpg
11e8e253b7fbaf641d76d7481b22671b
e9b5be7cb331e8c0b6e86787d6ef78b9d5ba3db0
730758 F20101203_AABBFO boutin_s_Page_05.jp2
b7101e81e7bac9ae2507dd29f6979b38
8eb7c9022cca0d21f30f6373ddd3506ad97da658
35593 F20101203_AABBKM boutin_s_Page_17.QC.jpg
e6e5f752d9228bbcf7075fe547b820e0
22c6394e8a571df8b4af60fe6f5748e113ec1361
116775 F20101203_AABBFP boutin_s_Page_06.jp2
5bf1f587d77d48a62e5af82a52ae292e
70e4d3957aae55bdfa923f0a65f0561a5b361bde
8915 F20101203_AABBKN boutin_s_Page_17thm.jpg
187aacabe870cbc27a45230ea2d922c9
d102cd45e6601b0fdae391f6137a638426dacea0
1051962 F20101203_AABBFQ boutin_s_Page_07.jp2
21f5b34d39288557ee62954062c7b570
d6535291acaaf6c2962bbb7df3d6959551adc251
36380 F20101203_AABBKO boutin_s_Page_18.QC.jpg
fba8d0d3d8cfab9e652315922e3623fd
12a0b36311e835661e12de839d15e666808bd666
142993 F20101203_AABBFR boutin_s_Page_08.jp2
7d0a5b155fce3c280ad0126963835d31
c7478b7f84dacd47182321063243a4f16182b080
8989 F20101203_AABBKP boutin_s_Page_18thm.jpg
7ea6b249578f59efd9991b3496f8c873
9b1e7fbf96cb4c50c2278390647b931dfeaef6d1
1051858 F20101203_AABBFS boutin_s_Page_09.jp2
ffbe47ef5029d70907859d791f6566b5
e80e9450545514754de82985556273eb2cd0044f
34916 F20101203_AABBKQ boutin_s_Page_19.QC.jpg
117cf482d0c1c55a804c18ac0e90a0f7
2ca81248517e99fecd354945a6f2628b7cad01a3
1051976 F20101203_AABBFT boutin_s_Page_10.jp2
cf768ea2a43a9b513ebce32122bea1e5
a1b0ff3e165734d6940722dc2d92c1f68d780e30
8398 F20101203_AABBKR boutin_s_Page_19thm.jpg
f3e570b622d6e9fd09487061d963bb06
2b78ad8725cb64a688936c8ede6ab396e55a39bf
1051973 F20101203_AABBFU boutin_s_Page_11.jp2
f1a18c0520bd7cc94cff543cd39ff8dc
e683d5eabecb3cb2c531b476dad412cd41671deb
1033750 F20101203_AABBFV boutin_s_Page_12.jp2
80b0568df29414ae4704d6f0477175cd
b1033df2f724a3cba39c20c3619480384d9d34f6
35712 F20101203_AABBKS boutin_s_Page_20.QC.jpg
a43ea44c317d47b2b249035140584609
63261717763e6fabc7c5f34a45ff9209dad7c126
1051919 F20101203_AABBFW boutin_s_Page_13.jp2
d610f1b76e86e042d533f8bd9e658e6e
a2ae9dd557071dd0f5ce7a4cd1de5ea10d15986d
34802 F20101203_AABBKT boutin_s_Page_21.QC.jpg
df71e19da351d4d03b593b025a2e5b1a
450ef62f87f41b221a24e1aae53a18c01600849b
1042801 F20101203_AABBFX boutin_s_Page_14.jp2
3a47231c21f0e05f87b854fe3e0cfc75
5e4d1b562b52bfb0bac87ebea65468fe647f5e43
8881 F20101203_AABBKU boutin_s_Page_21thm.jpg
96c48bb92b2c32122355b9b7178ce1ee
948798f0325f18076282b7b353d6d742db104305
F20101203_AABBFY boutin_s_Page_15.jp2
68316dee0b7e654aae3ac920d58de5b3
1c87f406e82ae2af214b49a24c97715dc40e1c5c
32873 F20101203_AABBKV boutin_s_Page_22.QC.jpg
b32be121f3a3c67b3f5aa617d3f756d3
75e198f77c06a90844b7baf693bdeb200f10821a
530829 F20101203_AABBDA boutin_s_Page_48.jp2
cd0148bf1285c716a1e9746bb5afbd45
11eed85215aaff4435e41f37e0d6e2f49d8e8d94
907396 F20101203_AABBFZ boutin_s_Page_16.jp2
58436c81690d34618a267e0fe4ae2b37
db9669050d10bb352e49b3a83884da7c732b0868
8080 F20101203_AABBKW boutin_s_Page_22thm.jpg
6c8c04ebba368cc3776ceeeb05303d87
73d3dcd7f8e115ffd105b1dc7a2923be63364283
1051982 F20101203_AABBDB boutin_s_Page_41.jp2
d6c6223eb9aa5b0bfb20519766b05d67
6a908adb94d565f5dc3db1a3ba32820810c1d215
35243 F20101203_AABBKX boutin_s_Page_23.QC.jpg
b87a65aaa256bd53faef6ff7f0d65971
31f08ace016245a1429aee55e537d6174bf9b730
F20101203_AABBDC boutin_s_Page_36.tif
eea7ae8631175f0cdbab2c2f60856050
6a04efc595521477f9cb23782465e5d93a841814
F20101203_AABBIA boutin_s_Page_19.tif
3d8d50c8849c4f73f3af4475757a3c19
9314ed9f70a4ed6bfa1a0b2dfec1fd04879b60cc
F20101203_AABBKY boutin_s_Page_23thm.jpg
8257c8f0a1259ffa2af81e6291b83e87
622610da6f6e304fdb9059c5246867008b180f90
106056 F20101203_AABBDD boutin_s_Page_09.jpg
d8628ce5b5046f50cdfaaa69bd2622f3
fe2de2e867d1c0bf9d429f43e301942011b6fb9d
F20101203_AABBIB boutin_s_Page_20.tif
7cb7ef27d540513e7775f9b8f4329d84
52452c6195868a187fa36944e92b194a1222ede9
35401 F20101203_AABBKZ boutin_s_Page_24.QC.jpg
69a446dac6029b9d946517193104d756
5bdafa45171fa6c2cab914a96831de2fd9b2c668
31923 F20101203_AABBDE boutin_s_Page_07.QC.jpg
94d22022a5c92c195274bb06fa724166
4c2c759b34568dc22f067a85db8123977db4660f
F20101203_AABBIC boutin_s_Page_21.tif
25473938e99c864fec644dbcddf757ab
feb9937fc73ba48dcf23ecaa63997c3cf03cc694
9194 F20101203_AABBDF boutin_s_Page_44thm.jpg
58ecdbcdef6c183113e8b056fc32c8a8
85c71d9d55c5bbce6c53ba72cd9d5c3bbc0f9d1c
6560 F20101203_AABBNA boutin_s_Page_51.QC.jpg
27d88cf64af76b02f42ba92017f2a737
5112405c372dfc4ba8c41dbf37a74b7dd17e01af
F20101203_AABBID boutin_s_Page_22.tif
0fe946b7f9a84c25e6d0661e62090584
1b036cd60bd6db3eb317e9b8167d1b4bf67a444d
F20101203_AABBDG boutin_s_Page_48.tif
7ed223f6008fb49036cd2e4ef9790272
a37be5ff74a2969ffc623c6357fe2dfd1a78c97f
1800 F20101203_AABBNB boutin_s_Page_51thm.jpg
51baad75791104f45e263bf3ce09609b
5d4fcc7c67619b91f0732ffbcd71ade849ed02b1
F20101203_AABBIE boutin_s_Page_23.tif
b63f7a9288715d58c4d088ea6562becd
37a3f35ab2f7525bb8d85ed6471635164f3b45bb
115256 F20101203_AABBDH boutin_s_Page_38.jpg
8814d231a7471fa4e05622288f1db576
388e34cfda84befd35133f26be2b093ea7789444
29035 F20101203_AABBNC boutin_s_Page_52.QC.jpg
e9587077340a0e9deed094c31e6a4899
e65e4059488defbcd815283dbb82a98c1855c0d6
F20101203_AABBIF boutin_s_Page_24.tif
c8c6958abf62a5b23ee7fca0b0c57c5a
53b093635c3d16a1efd2ec2ad75a5f64fa3593f4
61339 F20101203_AABBDI UFE0022264_00001.xml FULL
d8d1f9f181e3d4ee10737625911e8d83
eaef1f881d81dfe6bd92f79ab2c9f9b0efb46b43
F20101203_AABBIG boutin_s_Page_25.tif
b43493795f8788da1a7b6623fc1521d2
d643c3ce0065eeeb85f9faa35e0075d1143bcfd0
8014 F20101203_AABBND boutin_s_Page_52thm.jpg
60b646081ad3d9b7ba7ddbb2448422b3
d63c3ab3a6531b514a1b569afa28742261655492
F20101203_AABBIH boutin_s_Page_26.tif
6e5e00c97741df48c7c421512962c131
44c77cda5b314eb81d392312a7f28ae72ce50318
22391 F20101203_AABBNE boutin_s_Page_53.QC.jpg
92e0bfa600337c4c5adf7a44e9d92a6c
42f7a20f0f32869bdd7cbc44b54977c1a014d060
F20101203_AABBII boutin_s_Page_27.tif
4c597e2729910fd432f0aef9418e4317
656e59fda400f5815d3062cbc510d9eac5da1804
5823 F20101203_AABBNF boutin_s_Page_53thm.jpg
28f85b3c380428fdd0a1cc8548b677cf
03dfd4cb005db4576ee3de8fadf5327986fe0135
F20101203_AABBIJ boutin_s_Page_28.tif
caef04844e92eadee52b9c9d0b11481b
f8ccfa3aec9684d39140f2b2e8304ef6da34ea0a
23329 F20101203_AABBDL boutin_s_Page_01.jpg
169c115714ab1101f5d7a81995fbfc07
b977d9e18a2a99d1eec8519d43c695112e756005
10762 F20101203_AABBNG boutin_s_Page_54.QC.jpg
218c8bbfa693e0f82e28c08660148e7b
a7bb759d6e5022841086be51ce455b3e64aed7c2
F20101203_AABBIK boutin_s_Page_29.tif
ff17d91ecd93cf74d7c7116c1bc79869
027bdde5e874231deda30885230ed2bc17d4c99d
3638 F20101203_AABBDM boutin_s_Page_02.jpg
dc4f78588b5a2f3c0b3ce867d934fabe
b4a33969e4e17df1054a536ca072927a3b965a3e
2614 F20101203_AABBNH boutin_s_Page_54thm.jpg
1919625146cb44483d87fcc1691a6329
6023dd8123e1f3f39cc62ad86ccdd413fd1e7ac1
F20101203_AABBIL boutin_s_Page_30.tif
4657a0237fd1f4322e7475da2abd6752
c7e63f08aa35c8c066c403c66f3002be494008be
5141 F20101203_AABBDN boutin_s_Page_03.jpg
4c1de89e692f4cc5486ce27a4131575a
75651606b6fbe2c5203f55b207b2fd0968011543
42724 F20101203_AABBNI UFE0022264_00001.mets
9886a44f4a0adfb970b6cb3caba6384e
072a5c12264bf676f8c12cddc4e272e7b39a1e8f
F20101203_AABBIM boutin_s_Page_31.tif
9d1739e532306e3eec08bfd4e89d9993
fa06967791906e49a93e5fd8190ea72bdbb5bde3
33082 F20101203_AABBDO boutin_s_Page_04.jpg
06851c612daaa67cd579763352c4597a
6dcaf8a7295aee057d7ba69eb03167b20f200048
F20101203_AABBIN boutin_s_Page_32.tif
2abebc3634fc3e4aeeeab4795d263417
895290aa380e3d024c081471be572115ee26e2c2
43002 F20101203_AABBDP boutin_s_Page_05.jpg
eaae482c47453fa52cedd27686c597ea
30f95c652532b805c4c957c722ae358064830c7e
F20101203_AABBIO boutin_s_Page_33.tif
33aa297118e91f7e5b4276a6399e8847
2be4f8a26842bdbde40b143fbdaf8eec6683745b
12001 F20101203_AABBDQ boutin_s_Page_06.jpg
d657463f473f172ff2585d51edaa5ef0
8df83474316f5124b8ce07292f17f5b7670be38b
F20101203_AABBIP boutin_s_Page_34.tif
f9891e918cba76cc7f7d9637c507ed69
011db17e5ce9bb60750861a9fe9ed1d83494460c
100272 F20101203_AABBDR boutin_s_Page_07.jpg
a0e197fca2e6c10e74f2b10bdb03ab1d
7cbb95a6b565b140a81dcc4f15a9863215b3a96f
15533 F20101203_AABBDS boutin_s_Page_08.jpg
e1084dd2d1f154ec3bdb81a54fb04b47
65de20037a54fce8b3b80f7a25129b51469e9917
F20101203_AABBIQ boutin_s_Page_35.tif
37d37c5978c46f4bacbb4c067b39f5b8
9eaf3c0766daf07e1517f55ceedc2d3dee7e9fd0
107710 F20101203_AABBDT boutin_s_Page_10.jpg
78e96fe32d3c7f2f3b9be3cd03f8c676
7ffa93eaa5bae47004e756a17e97a762da8e79c1
F20101203_AABBIR boutin_s_Page_37.tif
a97be5ba94f769708933821dfbf0fdb7
f05dc5bf3c95370a4db9b2a9238fb97e77693b4c
113888 F20101203_AABBDU boutin_s_Page_11.jpg
2bb43d40f8073419015a2651de7a4e58
f0f34cff12c812cb13fefd11ed36849bcae529a6
F20101203_AABBIS boutin_s_Page_38.tif
d8f219234e70aea2b179e5c139b3430d
c5929fa49d1ad31eadd67aa214e92a616e915cf5
93779 F20101203_AABBDV boutin_s_Page_12.jpg
1fe4d30034ade93004f704c62876fe0f
9b16dd0a64737a8338085d6e30164a91c4277b53
F20101203_AABBIT boutin_s_Page_39.tif
c8b1208014b3e0955c1384e88934539f
aac9b1c194a6ef391520ba5aafc081f7b5e6df20
103736 F20101203_AABBDW boutin_s_Page_13.jpg
a86f76f2a936df75350f4093b10ba932
08f3639d76cbc24d2e794e5be910c1a4e612bc40
F20101203_AABBIU boutin_s_Page_40.tif
264504162f3c201d36a49714f2218596
f164da47a7a84d78a409799e51a9840c7e770713
94864 F20101203_AABBDX boutin_s_Page_14.jpg
2a3b6c3fd884de822eb0c42900492a94
32a8727bb42b1a03a8c542d39948607f13fb8e8c
F20101203_AABBIV boutin_s_Page_41.tif
99ac417acee2ebb4092a5640294be157
3800756331ae0217d5826c0001ac58920773123f
106227 F20101203_AABBDY boutin_s_Page_15.jpg
c0d507e59ed30bb200cce8b8d1e68e95
4e4485d48bdf1403ee89da39ae2a61e4ec0a2d61
F20101203_AABBIW boutin_s_Page_42.tif
2a9d82fc922853521d60d7129f1290c1
eec2c212c00642864d45ca26ee8586c402cdb02e
82317 F20101203_AABBDZ boutin_s_Page_16.jpg
f736316e659045825c59ecf4466dc63e
81d1967a8ebc476c450e4d2d88ad431c7831b632
F20101203_AABBIX boutin_s_Page_43.tif
b8c48abaf8e513ea6b75601a1cdd907b
f5c36dfc5dee48cdab08faa57e12713619ffd672
F20101203_AABBIY boutin_s_Page_44.tif
13c7688e0aaec67e2bfe8095b43116bc
7585a098cfa05a305f8abbd7a3f417ac73c10d94
1051977 F20101203_AABBGA boutin_s_Page_17.jp2
40abec723b8359940488170d762b6644
9b0562be0d709551712fa3c695ab1c34eaa45d0b
F20101203_AABBIZ boutin_s_Page_45.tif
ee4c83a451aa331cff7c00675699576b
247d20ecd113a6917f2171b9f4c44ad6d6c6627e
1051968 F20101203_AABBGB boutin_s_Page_18.jp2
dcd801d907491c45470e900dbc55bc7b
57c74f138394760dd2f3a5ac0e2affa2c74d0e6a
1051923 F20101203_AABBGC boutin_s_Page_19.jp2
7a6c1c22734529ac113a5998c154e652
a98f71c9cda9b545271fc1283cfa7fb52eb7cc2a
8782 F20101203_AABBLA boutin_s_Page_24thm.jpg
159244aa8a26c734a2f521ebbf93585c
5459eb82857fea0aa20cafffbde9343dc368a91a
1051924 F20101203_AABBGD boutin_s_Page_20.jp2
ff62ddc4bbb9f6ee3db05d3268c747bd
3455be52eb29927f9e2d7d48d6482459d711c931
36750 F20101203_AABBLB boutin_s_Page_25.QC.jpg
4bfa80f5e0f1f1901e012cd9790dc999
e1d7ca6b3d7a2e670458adbba97cf406df22e5bf
1051980 F20101203_AABBGE boutin_s_Page_21.jp2
e5822f0171d59cdb7bcec84f323241c9
9ecbe260b729e7e114984f30ebcf7ede1f18c1a0
9102 F20101203_AABBLC boutin_s_Page_25thm.jpg
59dfda50915487fb7d780b03cd0aad33
752c97a9c01fba6c52c25bf8782d65fde8dff5b2
1051940 F20101203_AABBGF boutin_s_Page_22.jp2
fd27f8a0d19cddfc306b9305d79846d5
fb6510c3f187e208de353fd5f0cae5d5908aa198
32832 F20101203_AABBLD boutin_s_Page_26.QC.jpg
8bace5c8a97323a644bb8467643c40b9
867c262720adbebd0887d2a49915236cfce1ca07
1051957 F20101203_AABBGG boutin_s_Page_23.jp2
5e2cc26150d0b122fbdc8b0ec975a18c
b10d1a812adefed00df6ecc3e4a39db9671e23bc
8144 F20101203_AABBLE boutin_s_Page_26thm.jpg
1eaac6b1df7015808a71b02c21099301
558fed7acdcb67a997c3bb442e5264e4c69a2ab0
1051970 F20101203_AABBGH boutin_s_Page_24.jp2
7079d7c718742afcdd0425ad7ff231a9
125eeba43860f941fbc589cab617557668e24f89
35239 F20101203_AABBLF boutin_s_Page_27.QC.jpg
661011c241c6befb102cd984d91430f3
ffc3e674a6dda3d6d3de4f69313786c451699c25
1051930 F20101203_AABBGI boutin_s_Page_25.jp2
a518330b2ea0d3c2dccba6c7d15976bf
72450a20e43834c0ccadb5ac13ad8071ea4f6aff
8612 F20101203_AABBLG boutin_s_Page_27thm.jpg
91d961afc371e124f002b48f8b57dec3
f5903bbefddeef89776d810f23e49b86a25579ac
1051972 F20101203_AABBGJ boutin_s_Page_26.jp2
fbba28a7cb73306efc61ee77afb49ff7
c0a5790399f043e7d96c42f864dd71618c391204
36106 F20101203_AABBLH boutin_s_Page_28.QC.jpg
5117424717ccbca1df311d24675e2f29
9b1fcdc758fa42b763d5490df462164d4468f905
1051984 F20101203_AABBGK boutin_s_Page_27.jp2
b97488e98b5bf989aebc73e98417004f
c7e9c2dae007498713b0108e2291b07c8b97c5ee
9041 F20101203_AABBLI boutin_s_Page_28thm.jpg
ad14cab0aff6d9c0376291b47954b62d
7c723decbfde3b56cc0c6f52588bb2f97171ceab
1051951 F20101203_AABBGL boutin_s_Page_28.jp2
fca0991267c82b49611c7aef9b35b86f
1951ec99ded44117e4b5447854dbdf767a047341
36794 F20101203_AABBLJ boutin_s_Page_29.QC.jpg
57791fa5c070adf83f98705b3caa0b34
e596995693570370002e42af5d3f48c54806aa87
1051916 F20101203_AABBGM boutin_s_Page_29.jp2
4eec2c7c492b7605cd2f00e115aa4199
40e27688b1937d01725311d8b699c6203f6c06b8
9093 F20101203_AABBLK boutin_s_Page_29thm.jpg
4b31059f01b78fecca1ecd7dfdcabbe4
c8aa72b36d580c488a1cf99bf99f8a6cef2c25d9
F20101203_AABBGN boutin_s_Page_30.jp2
d6d33c745237af765816463e301efb01
77edc6f901249318cd3c31ca878951bec2908abb
35539 F20101203_AABBLL boutin_s_Page_30.QC.jpg
7506000c70ba7398d5f00939c1dedaf9
bfabff425946232903861bc3c3fa8675e033dfb2
8779 F20101203_AABBLM boutin_s_Page_30thm.jpg
b4aceb7f9af634ba8dac43b6167b39d4
252c052aee1a9df6cdc37c453576ec5f2c119de1
519799 F20101203_AABBGO boutin_s_Page_31.jp2
9f8f5e6c5af1f035aa0ebccd21a32aed
88ff166254f6a104c8824a2caf570c909bd5d4f0
16225 F20101203_AABBLN boutin_s_Page_31.QC.jpg
98a6540f1656ed2b421f273b48eccbe1
4dfe4dde83d79a776cb6947524544299df29f282
1051966 F20101203_AABBGP boutin_s_Page_32.jp2
4d8a51c69681bf0bf41f220f2e583796
badd47d192aa7097de3c5aee8e78471473ffeddd
4126 F20101203_AABBLO boutin_s_Page_31thm.jpg
9f1eee92fcbad9326104ba423fdebaef
e963ad3ac33df60faae739c08166c687d14df32b
F20101203_AABBGQ boutin_s_Page_33.jp2
b84e93a18e6acebdfa1e69d2f8100b55
0181e2be2de6a3451d61ede4be4a1b2a4dd14b3a
32991 F20101203_AABBLP boutin_s_Page_32.QC.jpg
f3fd97597b0ae0d6e3ff1766338b1291
f47c2dd38a945396a387d62be4611d8a7c3dfbc4
1051983 F20101203_AABBGR boutin_s_Page_34.jp2
bf94326d50e222d2065445e510e503b0
97a0ee2f463b178d20901d7849321ec5a2cb8443
8412 F20101203_AABBLQ boutin_s_Page_32thm.jpg
55d65c2169e5ccc2242411c6746de7b5
572bcb89055b9650d84542c79bc7b7c926287e22
1051963 F20101203_AABBGS boutin_s_Page_35.jp2
3d44b778a8f2cbbbb377dac98b2e7e9e
7522befa1ccf1d348208cfae7c35e8e5c314875e
33882 F20101203_AABBLR boutin_s_Page_33.QC.jpg
ac74e85562362c454ed7e90c250d7ca9
553e3139fd35e347f83729b8045b4983ea094fa9
1051960 F20101203_AABBGT boutin_s_Page_36.jp2
834ca1cc32e7749eaabdb45f146e8046
b793b993ffc322294e2795f90f75b3687b77066c
8557 F20101203_AABBLS boutin_s_Page_33thm.jpg
20991cc8ad3cfc3397bce3d419b24063
eed85898df203d05ca87f7de55d052161f9d90ff
1051965 F20101203_AABBGU boutin_s_Page_37.jp2
192c1c0f545c64d4706702ac6a88a11a
d7177e9b51a381b88bc420e9971c9586d0c4230b
F20101203_AABBGV boutin_s_Page_38.jp2
9d4771bb4d29132214c7df2e2806f9d8
b7b5888563ed91610f30ae3142600ce9dc9ef4fa
37516 F20101203_AABBLT boutin_s_Page_34.QC.jpg
d57976776c93212b75924b725f0d9431
3e6d5acb20137d480db37f02176c86f5aeec6cd3
1051958 F20101203_AABBGW boutin_s_Page_39.jp2
8cce6797d74d9acb3264170f9590b9e1
55c47a058d1ad51e5d25986ff57426c12d1acdf2
9095 F20101203_AABBLU boutin_s_Page_34thm.jpg
c178436f8efab0dd142d402eb708fb5d
00d9f87a6f67e79c457e998c20bbe27f3ec3a806
F20101203_AABBGX boutin_s_Page_40.jp2
5e6bd5e576d895e27a34044f76023b26
f4d2192de44dc7d4b59c38883bec934f46f6e46c