<%BANNER%>

The Corpus Hermeticum

Permanent Link: http://ufdc.ufl.edu/UFE0021897/00001

Material Information

Title: The Corpus Hermeticum A Mirror for the Evolution of Christian Orthodoxy
Physical Description: 1 online resource (62 p.)
Language: english
Publisher: University of Florida
Place of Publication: Gainesville, Fla.
Publication Date: 2008

Subjects

Subjects / Keywords: alexandria, antiquity, apuleius, asclepius, astrology, augustine, berlinerblau, bourdieu, boyarin, christian, constantine, corpus, demiurge, demon, digeser, egypt, egyptian, firmicus, fowden, heresy, heretic, hermes, hermetic, hermeticum, lactantius, logos, magic, maternus, neoplatonism, orthodox, pagan, plato, porphyry, religion, yates
History -- Dissertations, Academic -- UF
Genre: History thesis, M.A.
bibliography   ( marcgt )
theses   ( marcgt )
government publication (state, provincial, terriorial, dependent)   ( marcgt )
born-digital   ( sobekcm )
Electronic Thesis or Dissertation

Notes

Abstract: The Corpus Hermeticum of Hermes Trismegistus and the Latin Asclepius traveled throughout the late ancient Christian world, both venerated as the most ancient and praiseworthy path to enlightenment and disdained as a failed philosophy fit only for derision and censure. Having disappeared in Europe through most of the Middle Ages, the Corpus reemerged in Renaissance Italy with even greater authority such that Marsilio Ficino put aside his translations of Plato to address Hermes, believed to be the far more ancient philosophy. This study traces the reactions to and uses of the Corpus Hermeticum during a period of emerging Christian orthodoxy in late antiquity. Augustine used the Corpus in the fifth century to distinguish proper Christian belief from heterodoxy, attacking man-made gods and using Hermes? words to demonstrate the false trickery of demons. Earlier Christian writers, however, were more ambivalent about the teachings of the Corpus. Lactantius found the demons of Hermes to be enemies of God but appealed to the mythic author as an authority to prove the superiority of Christian faith over demonic influence. Julius Firmicus Maternus, a pagan astrologer converted to Christianity, used the Corpus and the authority of Hermes in both his astrological and later anti-pagan works. Through an examination of these variant interpretations, the Hermetic tradition can be used as a tool for probing not only the emergence of Christian orthodoxy, but the formation of borders between pagan and Christian and the growing power of orthodoxy. The Corpus Hermeticum reveals a syncretistic interpenetration of Egyptian, Greek, and early Christian theology and cosmology. Held up as a mirror to ongoing intellectual transformation, the unchanging Corpus reflects the changing perspectives of both pagan and Christian thinkers during critical moments of cultural and religious evolution.
General Note: In the series University of Florida Digital Collections.
General Note: Includes vita.
Bibliography: Includes bibliographical references.
Source of Description: Description based on online resource; title from PDF title page.
Source of Description: This bibliographic record is available under the Creative Commons CC0 public domain dedication. The University of Florida Libraries, as creator of this bibliographic record, has waived all rights to it worldwide under copyright law, including all related and neighboring rights, to the extent allowed by law.
Thesis: Thesis (M.A.)--University of Florida, 2008.
Local: Adviser: Sterk, Andrea L.
Electronic Access: RESTRICTED TO UF STUDENTS, STAFF, FACULTY, AND ON-CAMPUS USE UNTIL 2010-05-31

Record Information

Source Institution: UFRGP
Rights Management: Applicable rights reserved.
Classification: lcc - LD1780 2008
System ID: UFE0021897:00001

Permanent Link: http://ufdc.ufl.edu/UFE0021897/00001

Material Information

Title: The Corpus Hermeticum A Mirror for the Evolution of Christian Orthodoxy
Physical Description: 1 online resource (62 p.)
Language: english
Publisher: University of Florida
Place of Publication: Gainesville, Fla.
Publication Date: 2008

Subjects

Subjects / Keywords: alexandria, antiquity, apuleius, asclepius, astrology, augustine, berlinerblau, bourdieu, boyarin, christian, constantine, corpus, demiurge, demon, digeser, egypt, egyptian, firmicus, fowden, heresy, heretic, hermes, hermetic, hermeticum, lactantius, logos, magic, maternus, neoplatonism, orthodox, pagan, plato, porphyry, religion, yates
History -- Dissertations, Academic -- UF
Genre: History thesis, M.A.
bibliography   ( marcgt )
theses   ( marcgt )
government publication (state, provincial, terriorial, dependent)   ( marcgt )
born-digital   ( sobekcm )
Electronic Thesis or Dissertation

Notes

Abstract: The Corpus Hermeticum of Hermes Trismegistus and the Latin Asclepius traveled throughout the late ancient Christian world, both venerated as the most ancient and praiseworthy path to enlightenment and disdained as a failed philosophy fit only for derision and censure. Having disappeared in Europe through most of the Middle Ages, the Corpus reemerged in Renaissance Italy with even greater authority such that Marsilio Ficino put aside his translations of Plato to address Hermes, believed to be the far more ancient philosophy. This study traces the reactions to and uses of the Corpus Hermeticum during a period of emerging Christian orthodoxy in late antiquity. Augustine used the Corpus in the fifth century to distinguish proper Christian belief from heterodoxy, attacking man-made gods and using Hermes? words to demonstrate the false trickery of demons. Earlier Christian writers, however, were more ambivalent about the teachings of the Corpus. Lactantius found the demons of Hermes to be enemies of God but appealed to the mythic author as an authority to prove the superiority of Christian faith over demonic influence. Julius Firmicus Maternus, a pagan astrologer converted to Christianity, used the Corpus and the authority of Hermes in both his astrological and later anti-pagan works. Through an examination of these variant interpretations, the Hermetic tradition can be used as a tool for probing not only the emergence of Christian orthodoxy, but the formation of borders between pagan and Christian and the growing power of orthodoxy. The Corpus Hermeticum reveals a syncretistic interpenetration of Egyptian, Greek, and early Christian theology and cosmology. Held up as a mirror to ongoing intellectual transformation, the unchanging Corpus reflects the changing perspectives of both pagan and Christian thinkers during critical moments of cultural and religious evolution.
General Note: In the series University of Florida Digital Collections.
General Note: Includes vita.
Bibliography: Includes bibliographical references.
Source of Description: Description based on online resource; title from PDF title page.
Source of Description: This bibliographic record is available under the Creative Commons CC0 public domain dedication. The University of Florida Libraries, as creator of this bibliographic record, has waived all rights to it worldwide under copyright law, including all related and neighboring rights, to the extent allowed by law.
Thesis: Thesis (M.A.)--University of Florida, 2008.
Local: Adviser: Sterk, Andrea L.
Electronic Access: RESTRICTED TO UF STUDENTS, STAFF, FACULTY, AND ON-CAMPUS USE UNTIL 2010-05-31

Record Information

Source Institution: UFRGP
Rights Management: Applicable rights reserved.
Classification: lcc - LD1780 2008
System ID: UFE0021897:00001


This item has the following downloads:


Full Text

PAGE 1

THE CORPUS HERMETICUM: A MIRROR FOR THE EVOLUTION OF CHRISTIAN ORTHODOXY By CHARLES FLOWERS A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLOR IDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA 2008 1

PAGE 2

2008 Charles Flowers 2

PAGE 3

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Even an activity as solitary as researchi ng history is never accomplished without the ongoing support and encouragement of others. To begin my foray into history, Sandy and Jimmy Pozzetta, Dr. Fred Gregory, and Dr. Jeff Needell were all instrumental in helping me move from one career to enter an entirely new one Without their confidence, I could not have taken my initial steps. For the hard part of writing history--from anal ysis and understanding, to forming my own voice and gaining confidence in my own opinion--I am completely in debt to Dr. Andrea Sterk, Dr. Nina Caput o, and Dr. Howard Louthan. They have shared their time, skills, and opinions to make me a better histor ian and in the process, I have gained not only colleagues, but friends. Without their encourag ement, I would never have succeeded along this journey. But my greatest thanks go to my wife Nikkie. The experience of extracting ideas from my head and having them appear coherent on the writ ten page has not always been a pleasant one. She has endured many days in which my doubts threatened to overcome my progress. Throughout, she has always supported me and helped me to take the next step. Without her love, my success would have no meaning. 3

PAGE 4

TABLE OF CONTENTS page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS...............................................................................................................3 ABSTRACT.....................................................................................................................................5 1 INTRODUCTION................................................................................................................. .......7 Goals.........................................................................................................................................7 The Commentators on the Corpus ..........................................................................................10 2 LACTANTIUS...........................................................................................................................13 Late Antique Culture and the Divine Institutes ......................................................................14 The One God of Lactantius.....................................................................................................17 3 FIRMICUS MATERNUS...........................................................................................................24 The Pagan:The Theory of Astrology in Eight Books ...............................................................26 The Christian:The Error of the Pagan Religions ....................................................................29 4 AUGUSTINE..............................................................................................................................36 Early Writings................................................................................................................. ........37 City of God ..............................................................................................................................40 5 CONCLUSION...........................................................................................................................49 The Corpus and Religion........................................................................................................50 The Corpus and Heresy..........................................................................................................51 The Corpus and Doxa .............................................................................................................53 LIST OF REFERENCES...............................................................................................................56 Primary Sources................................................................................................................ ......56 Secondary Sources.............................................................................................................. ....57 BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH.........................................................................................................62 4

PAGE 5

Abstract of Dissertation Pres ented to the Graduate School of the University of Florida in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts THE CORPUS HERMETICUM: A MIRROR FOR THE EVOLUTION OF CHRISTIAN ORTHODOXY By Charles Flowers May 2008 Chair: Andrea Sterk Major: History The Corpus Hermeticum of Hermes Trismegistus and the Latin Asclepius traveled throughout the late ancient Christ ian world, both venerated as the most ancient and praiseworthy path to enlightenment and disdained as a faile d philosophy fit only for derision and censure. Having disappeared in Europe thro ugh most of the Middle Ages, the Corpus reemerged in Renaissance Italy with even greater authority such that Marsilio Ficino put aside his translations of Plato to address Hermes, believed to be the far more ancient philosophy. This study traces the reacti ons to and uses of the Corpus Hermeticum during a period of emerging Christian orthodoxy in late antiquity. Augustine used the Corpus in the fifth century to distinguish proper Christian belief from heterodoxy, attackin g man-made gods and using Hermes words to demonstrate the false trickery of demons. Earlier Christian writers, however, were more ambivalent a bout the teachings of the Corpus Lactantius found the demons of Hermes to be enemies of God but appealed to th e mythic author as an authority to prove the superiority of Christian faith over demonic infl uence. Julius Firmicus Maternus, a pagan astrologer converted to Christianity, used the Corpus and the authority of Hermes in both his astrological and later anti-pagan works. 5

PAGE 6

6 Through an examination of these variant interp retations, the Hermetic tradition can be used as a tool for probing not only the emergence of Christian orthodoxy, but the formation of borders between pagan and Christian and th e growing power of orthodoxy. The Corpus Hermeticum reveals a syncretistic interp enetration of Egyptian, Greek, an d early Christian theology and cosmology. Held up as a mirror to ongoing intellectual transformation, the unchanging Corpus reflects the changing perspectives of both pagan and Christian thinkers during critical moments of cultural and religious evolution.

PAGE 7

CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION In 1463, Cosimo de Medici came to his tr anslator, Marsilio Ficino, telling him to interrupt his translation of the works of Plat o because a far more important manuscript had appeared in Florence. The works of Hermes Tr ismegistus, believed to be far more ancient and authoritative than Plato, or even Mo ses, required immediate attention.1 Plato could wait. By the time of the Renaissance, the reputation of He rmes for knowledge, piety, magic, and power had grown to such an extent that the arrival of the Corpus Hermeticum would help to usher in a revival of magic.2 A series of eighteen treatises, the Corpus passed on the revealed wisdom of a man-become-god, an amalgamation of the Hellenic god Hermes (or Mercury) and the Egyptian god Thoth, a man often referred to simply as the Egyptian.3 Over a thousand years earlier, however, in the Late Antiquity of No rth Africa and the Mediterranean, the Corpus was viewed very differently by numerous authors, as a comp etitive alternative to nascent Christianity. Beyond his (even then) ancient reputation, Hermes and the Corpus was representative of the hardening border line between pagan a nd Christian in the late Roman world. Goals The primary goal of this study is to exam ine the changing conceptions of Christian orthodoxy as reflected in the us e and interpretation of the Corpus Hermeticum by various Latin Christian writers of the fourth and fifth century. In selecting the passage s and issues they chose 1 Frances Yates, Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964), 1215. 2 Ibid., 18. 3 Brian P. Copenhaver, Hermetica:The Greek Corpus Hermeticum a nd the Latin Asclepiu s in a new English translation with notes and introduction (Cambridge: Cambridge University Pre ss, 1992), xli. Ficinos translation contained the first fourteen treatises and the Asclepius Additional treatises were adde d in the sixteenth century. All quoted portions of the Hermetica are taken from this Copenhaver refe rence. References will site the Corpus Hermeticum the treatise number as referenced by Copenhaver, and the page number. The Asclepius does not have a treatise number and will be referenced as Asclepius 7

PAGE 8

to address, Late Antique Christ ian authors presented particular views of an evolving doctrine. Pre-Nicene theologians like Tertullian appealed to Hermes as an ancient authority who could support individual concepts like the su rvival of the soul after death.4 Lactantius found in Hermes not only a prophecy of the coming of Ch ristianity, but broad support for Christian doctrine on the Son and the created world.5 The preand post-convers ion writings of Firm Maternus demonstrate how ideas within the Corpus began to enter Christian orthodoxy contemporaneously with the growing intolerance of a religion newly asce ndant in the po world. With increasing conflict in the Church over doctrinal issues, the syncretism present in Corpus became grounds for attack. icus litical the of er 6 In the aftermath of the C ouncil of Nicaea, descriptions the demiurge and the implications of a second created god found in the Corpus were no long acceptable. Marcellus of Ancyra attacked the theology of the Arians, claiming the Eusebian Logos to be a heresy inspired by Hermes. By the time of Augu stines assault on the Corpus in 417ce, the demons of Hermes, instructors in the magical arts, had become the embodiment of eternal misery and the deceivers of humanit y. The Bishop of Hippo would find ample support for his harsh treatment of the pagan gods in the growing body of legislation against paganism, soon to be compiled in the Theodosian Code.7 Unlike earlier theologians, Augustine found that the theological concep ts espoused in the Corpus Hermeticum could have few redeeming qualities. They were antithetical to his theology of mediation and dire ctly contradicted the 4 Garth Fowden, The Egyptian Hermes:A Historical Approach to the Late Pagan Mind (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), 198. Fowden notes that Tertullia n was the first African Christia n to quote directly from the Hermetica in support of the transmigration of souls. 5 Lactantius deals extensively with the Asclepius in the original Greek in the Divine Institutes. See Book 1, Ch 6 for Hermes knowledge of the One God; Book 2, Ch 15 on the origin of demons and Ch 16 for the protection from demons available to the faithful; Book 4, Ch 6 for the Son of God according to Hermes and Ch 9 for the Logos. 6 Fowden, 208-209. See also note 79, this page, for the Marcellus of Ancyra reference to Eusebius and Hermes. 8

PAGE 9

importance of the nature and role of Christ wh ich would soon be taken up at the Council of Ephesus in 431ce. A secondary goal is to examin e more broadly the formation of religion in general. 8 This conversation will necessarily be limited, given the scope of this paper, but will act as a way to introduce a theoretical framew ork which will provide additional questions to explore in the sources. Daniel Boyarin recommends to begin with the texts or assemblages to understand and that theory is a way to engage with pr oblems in texts and for generating problems.9 Following this recommendation, my concluding remarks w ill show that as a shared document between Christian authors the Corpus Hermeticum can be used to examine the underlying social and philosophical basis of the Late Antique world. The uses of the Corpus presented here provide concrete examples for the theoretical definitions of symbolic power and the emergence of heresy. Under the auspices of the Roman Empire, Christianity was in the process of red acting its core texts and determining its doctrinal course. The confused and sometimes self-contradictory treatises of the Corpus demonstrate where a similar process of pagan identity formation failed completely in the shadow of Christian self-def inition, despite the best efforts of Iamblichus to define a pagan religion, or Julian to promote it.10 The first through fifth centuries witnessed this 7 The Theodosian Code and Novels and the Sirmondian Constitutions ed. Clyde Pharr (P rinceton: Princeton University Press, 1952). See in particular Book 9 for ma gic and Book 11 for pardons (o r lack thereof). See also Book 16, Title 5 for Christian heretics and Title 10 for laws curtailing paganism. 8 ric Rebillard discusses the cautious use of patristic citations by Augustine as a new fourth-century style supporting Christian argument beyond that provided by Scripture. The use of Hermes and the writings attributed to him across these early Christian writers suggests a parallel development in the use of pagan citations for Christian argument. As a third goal, examining the development of Hermetic citation as a particular style of discourse along these lines has not been possible in this paper. ric Rebillard, A New Style of Argument in Christian Polemic: Augustine and the Use of Patristic Citations, in The Journal of Early Christian Studies 8:4 (2000): 559-578. 9 Conversations with Dr. Daniel Boyarin during his presentation at the University of Florida in the Spring of 2007. 10 Iamblichus was a third-century Neoplatonist who relie d heavily on the Hermetica in his construction of a coherent set of pagan practices and doctrines in De Mysteriis Iamblichus is also the source envisioned by Emperor Julian the Apostate in his attempt to revive paga nism against the Galileans. See Gregory Shaw, Theurgy and the 9

PAGE 10

invention of Christianity as a religion while the Corpus Hermeticum fell first into a middle ground and later into pure pagan error, reflecting the changing definition of orthodoxy.11 The Commentators on the Corpus When held up as a mirror to ongoing intellectual transformation, the uses of and responses to the Corpus reflect the changing perspectives of Christian thinkers during critical moments of cultural a nd religious evolution.12 For Lactantius, convincing pagans that Christianity was a short step fr om a monotheistic belief in the One god to the proper worship of the Christian God was a primary goal of his Divine Institutes But these beliefs (particularly his acceptance of the concept of the Logos as a se cond god) were found to be incomplete at the Council of Nicaea. The writings of Firmicus Mate rnus, a recent convert, re flect the mind of an educated Roman elite during a period of hardening of Roman law against paganism in general. Where earlier scholars may have seen inconsiste ncies in Firmicus, the image of Firmicus reflected by the Corpus is that of a zealous convert abandoning pagan ideas and embracing the theological possibilities of a redemp tive Christ, as well as the coerci ve power of the state. This same brand of internal consistency is particularly evident in the case of Augustine. In analyzing the encounter between the Bishop of Hippo and Apuleius in City of God Vincent Hunink asks not only why Augustine would devote such space to the innocent little speech about demons in De Deo Socratis, but he also wonders at the misrepre sentation of Apulei uss views and the Soul: The Neoplatonism of Iamblichus (The Pennsylvania University Press: University Park, PA, 1995) for the definitive treatment of his philosophy and Iamblichus. See De Mysteriis, ed. Emma C. Clarke, John M. Dillon, & Jackson P. Hershbell (Leiden: Brill, 2004) for a recent translation with facing English and Greek text. 11 Daniel Boyarin, Border Lines: The Partition of Judeo-Christianity (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2004), 202. 12 This thesis is the first portion of a substan tial project intended to trace the uses of the Corpus (and Hermetica in general) through Late Antiquity, providing a reference for a broad selection of authors that reacted to the Corpus The period introduced here, from approximately 200ce to 450ce, encompass a Masters Thesis. Additional work with the Corpus in paganism, Islam, Medieval Europe, and the Early Modern Period will constitute the chapters of a future PhD dissertation. 10

PAGE 11

exclusion of the positive as pects of Apuleian theory.13 It is the contention of this paper that Augustine employs both Apuleius and the Corpus together in a single logical construction to discredit pagan Neoplatonism and strengthen his Christian alternative. William C. Grese has traced points of contact between the thirteenth treatise in the Corpus and early Christian and Gnostic literature, detailing each, in a line-by-line exploration of the work. As he himself notes, however, his study is only a beginning of the i nvestigation into the history of the Hermetic tradition, and indeed is lim ited to only a single treatise.14 To my knowledge, there have been no other examinations of early Christian appropriations of or objections to the Corpus along the lines of either Greses meticulous methodology or the broad-based approach which I explore in this paper. Lactantius, Firmicus Maternus, and Augustine use the Corpus to define a border between pagan and Christian, and over the century and a half separating their writings that border becomes not only clearer but exclusionary. Boya rins designation of the late fourth and early fifth centuries as the critical period not only for the separation of Christian and Jewish faiths, but the solidification of religion in its modern definition is further supported by the evidence presented here. Lactantius affords a glimpse of Christianity in transition in that he found easy parallels between his Christian faith and pa gan philosophy. Monotheism was not a wholly owned subsidiary of Christianity, but would beco me so as Christians employed their symbolic capital to create and shape othe r groups. Later in the centur y, the lines between these groups were further defined. Firmicus Maternus may have been turning his pen from pagan pursuits to Christian polemics for political gain under a ne w regime, but the concepts he drew upon for his 13Vincent Hunink, 'Apuleius, qui nobi s Afris afer est notior': Augustine's polemic against Apuleius in De Civitate Dei, in Scholia: Studies in Classical Antiquity 12 (2003): 82-95. 14 William C. Grese, Corpus Hermeticum XIII an d Early Christian Literature (Leiden: Brill, 1979). 11

PAGE 12

12 attacks demonstrate the process of a shared cultural he ritage undergoing forcef ul separation. By the time of Augustine, that process was larg ely complete. In his quotations from the Corpus Augustine can afford to be apologetic on behalf of Hermes since the danger posed by pagan ideas of divinity has passed. The similarities f ound by Lactantius become dangerous errors to be stamped out by Firmicus and then, finally, merely mistakes of a pre-Christian people as seen by Augustine.

PAGE 13

CHAPTER 2 LACTANTIUS Traveling from North Africa, Lactantius had ar rived in Nicomedia in 302ce to take up an endowed chair of rhetoric, summoned to the court by Diocletian as an instructor in Latin and editor of official Latin writings.1 R. M. Ogilvie has produced an exhaustive comparative study of Lactantius and his literary quotations, concludi ng that Lactantius receiv ed a typical classical education but had very little access to original works in his most productive writing years.2 However, Ogilvie does conclude that Lactantius not only knew the Herme tica well but may have had direct access to the texts themselves.3 Lactantius quotes most often from a Greek version of the Asclepius which he calls the Summo Perfectus ( Perfect Discourse ) that is no longer extant and was more accurate than the Latin Asclepius He also quotes from Hermetic works beyond the Corpus Hermeticum which are seen later only in Stob aeus and Cyril of Alexandria. His access to these texts is in keeping with thei r general spread through the eastern Empire. Iamblichus, a student of Porphyry, relied he avily on Hermes Trismegistus in his On the Mysteries written in 300ce to support his progra m to create a unified pagan religion.4 Lactantiuss classical and even Bibl ical quotations are more likely from florilegia betraying the central position that Hermes t ook in his own personal philosophy.5 1 R. M. Ogilvie, The Library of Lactantius (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 1. See also H. A. Drake, Constantine and the Bishops: The Politics of Intolerance (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2000), 207-212. 2 Ogilvie, 4-6. 3 Ibid., 28-36. 4 Elizabeth DePalma Digeser, The Making of a Christian Empire: Lactantius & Rome (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2000), 66-67. 5 Ibid., 35. 13

PAGE 14

Late Antique Culture and the Divine Institutes It was during the palace lectures of the follo wing winter of 303ce in Nicomedia that the toleration of Christian practices ende d and the Great Persecution began.6 As a recent convert to Christianity, a teacher, and an acco mplished rhetor, Lactantius wrote the Divine Institutes from 305-310ce to counter the arguments made during those lectures by the pagan philoso Porphyry, a figure who will appear frequently in this discussion, and the vehemently antiChristian governor of Bithynia, Hierocles. pher 7 Lactantius had found that there have been wanting among us (Christians) suitable trained and skillf ul teachers who would vehemently and keenly refute public errors.8 Hermes appears in all key sections of the Institutes including discussions on false worship and how it originated, true wisdom and the resulting true worship, and how this worship leads to a happy life. Throughout thes e books, he employed the authority of Hermes Trismegistus and ideas from the Corpus Hermeticum to support a Christian interpretation of the One God, attempting to bolster support for the acceptance of Christianity. Lactantiuss Institutes not only reveal a very fluid border between Christian concepts and those of the Corpus but also reflect the most heated theologi cal discussions of the times, incl uding the divine nature of God, the creation of humanity, and how humanity can co me to know God. Writing within a century of the most probable date of publication for ma ny of the Hermetic treatises, Lactantius demonstrates that ideas current to pagan monot heism enabled Christian apologists to find and 6 Ibid., 2. 7 Ibid, 5. Digeser is clearly convinced that the pagan philosopher whom L actantius addresses in the Divine Institutes is Porphyry, although this attribution has not been conclusively proven to the satisfaction of some Late Antique historians. See her complete argument in Eli zabeth DePalma Digeser, Lactantius, Porphyry, and the Debate over Religious Toleration, in The Journal of Roman Studies 88 (1998): 129-146 for a thorough comparative analysis of the Divine Institutes and Porphyrys Philosophy from Oracles 8 For Lactantius, see The Divine Institutes, Books I-VII trans. Mary Francis McDonald in The Fathers of the Church, Vol. 49 (Washington D. C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1964), 330. All references to the Divine Institutes are taken from this translation. Book, ch apter, and page numbers will be included. 14

PAGE 15

exploit common ground with pagans.9 Focusing on shared monothe istic issues, Lactantius also finds Hermetic support for attacks on Roman polytheism. The manner in which the Corpus was used either to enhance or support key Christian co ncepts, particularly thos e issues taken up at the early Ecumenical Councils, will be a key theme to my examination. Lactantius finds support for his conception of God when Hermes vouches for the majesty of the supreme and single God and he calls Hi m by the same names which we use: Lord and Father.10 This Hermetic God is greater than any name and is nameless or rather he is allnamed since he is one and all,11 and Lactantius agreed that b ecause He is always one, the proper name is God.12 However, it was not the oneness or namelessness of God that troubled pagans like Porphyry;13 instead it was the Christian asser tion that Christ, a human being, was also the same ineffable One God. But here too, Lactantius could find ample support in the Hermetica. The Asclepius explains that God, made a god next after himself;14 Lactantiuss translation of the next sentences reflects the sa me idea: He made this one, the first and only and one He was delighted with him, a nd loved him perfectly as his own son.15 The first treatise of the Corpus Hermeticum relates that the lightgiving word who comes from mind [which is God the Father] is the son of god and that they are not divided from one another for their union 9 There is very little evidence available for the exact dating of Hermetic texts including the Corpus Hermeticum Generally accepted dating places their creation between the la te first and late third centu ries. See Fowden, 10-11. 10 Lactantius, Divine Institutes I.6, 32. Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum II.17, 12. 11 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum V.10, 20 and Asclepius .20, 78. 12 Lactantius, Divine Institutes I.6, 32. 13 Digeser, The Making of a Christian Empire 5-7. 14 Copenhaver, Asclepius 8, 71. 15 Lactantius, Divine Institutes IV.6, 256. Reiterated in his Epitome .42. 15

PAGE 16

is life.16 Here Lactantius found support for the idea of a son of God, consubstantial with the Father, who also matched the Neoplat onic and Christian conception of the Logos the divine word of God embodied in a man. Lactantius used the Corpus to show that pagan and Christian were not nearly as far apart in their beliefs as the polemic Porphyry may have presumed. By using the Hermetica as a source of support, Lactantius positioned himself squarely in an already existent middle ground between pagan a nd Christian beliefs. Further evidence for the existence of such a middle ground can be found in the monotheistic cult of Theos Hypsistos which had spread throughout Asia Minor during the third and fourth centu ries. This greatest God is found in both the Old Testament and in oracular inscriptions from Lycia and bears striking resemblance to the description of the He rmetic god: Born of its elf, untaught, without a mother, unshakeable, not contained in a name, kn own by many names, dwelling in fire, this is god.17 Stephen Mitchell argues th at older scholarship which fo cuses on distinguishing pagan from Jewish uses of this name for God is mist aken. Instead, he favors the explanation that the cult had room for pagans and fo r Jews with the cult acting as a seed-bed into which Jewish and Christian theology c ould readily be planted.18 The well-developed Jewish theology allowed the cult to appeal not ju st to ordinary people, but to the highly-educated, Neop philosophers whom Lact antius was targeting. latonic 19 Lactantius himself did not let this cult go unnoticed. There are only two writ ten sources in Late Antiquity wh ich quote these three lines in Greek; one is the fifth-century Theosophy of Tubingen, the other is the Divine Institutes .20 16 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum I, 2. 17 Stephen Mitchell, The Cult of Theos Hypsistos between Pagans, Jews, and Christians, in Pagan Monotheism in Late Antiquity ed. Polymnia Athanassiadi and Michael Fr ede (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), 86. 18 Ibid., 115 and 128. 19 Ibid., 127. 20 Ibid., 86. Lactantius, Divine Institutes I.7, 35. 16

PAGE 17

Lactantius did not have to cr oss a well-defined boundary either for evidence of monotheistic beliefs or for receptive groups who might accept Christian ideas. Although Lactantius finds a series of helpful comparisons with the Hermetic god and Theos Hypsistos, his conception of the Christian God is clearly binitari an, almost completely lacking any concept of a Holy Spirit. Since the trinity itself is not addressed until the Council of Constantinople in 381, modern critiques of his theological position neither weaken Lactanti uss Christian conviction nor endanger his ultimate goal of pagan conversion. Hermeticism helps to securely site Lactantius within the broad territory of La te Antique religious thought since it is not his Christianity which is in doubt. Instead, it is the an achronistic attempt to clearly de lineate pagan from Christian (or Jew) which must be abandoned to allow for the interaction of a broad class of monotheistic beliefs as seen in the sources.21 The One God of Lactantius Seeking to prove to potential monotheistic paga n converts that the Chri stian version of the One God was not just identical, but superior, to the One God of the Platonists, the Corpus further afforded him the opportunity to attack polytheism. Lactantius brings up the testimony of the Sibyls and Hermes not only for support of Christia n concepts, but also as proof that the pagan gods are nothing more than ancient human bei ngs who achieved renown. In Book I, Chapter VIII he asserts that since the pagan tales of the birth of Apoll o, Mercury, and Hercules involved a father and mother; that they were simply men.22 The un-created, un-nameable nature of God, 21 Ibid., 115. Mitchells elegant and forceful idea is wo rth quoting in full: More than that it shows that the principal categories into which we divide the religious groupings of late antiquity are simply inappropriate or misleading when applied to the beliefs and practices of a significant proportion of the population of the eastern Roman empire. 22 Lactantius, Divine Institutes I.8, 38-39. See also I.15, 64. See Lactantius, Epitome .2 for a succinct explanation of the limited power of the multitude of pagan gods, again proving that none of them meet the qualifications of a Christian God worthy of worship. 17

PAGE 18

also supported earlier by Hermes, was foundational for his attack on the pagan gods. He claims that the gods were just powerful men from earlie st history, lending their names and character to rivers, streams, and legends. So it must not be wondered at if the names of those who gave birth to exceedingly powerful kings we re assigned to heaven and earth.23 Hermes himself asserts this euhemeristic id eal by explaining that Ouranos and Kronos were his own living ancestors who had been deified after death.24 For Lactantius, then, paga ns are mistaken in their worship of gods who were only the legendary fi rst rulers of the earth. Lactantius neither denies the existence of these beings nor does he blame the poets of the pagan literary tradition for transmitting their legend.25 Lactantius simply concluded that the notion that these humans could have created the universe was wrong. From their births and deaths, the pagan gods were simply not sufficient: I seek a God beyond whom there is nothing whatsoever, who is the fount and origin of things. Of necessity this One must exist, who esta blished heaven itself and founded the earth.26 Beyond the nature of God and humanity, Lactanti us found affinity with Hermetic writing on how humanity could come to know a nameless God. From piety, reverence, and fear to prayer and prophecy, Hermes and Asclepius s upported a Christian understanding of God, but also pointed to the superiority of Christian be lief over its pagan opponents. Both Hermes and Lactantius agreed that God revealed many thi ngs while keeping others secret since it is 23 Lactantius, Divine Institutes I.11, 54. 24 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum X.5, 31. See also notes on 157. 25 Louis Swift, Arnobius and Lactantius: Two Views of the Pagan Poets, in Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 96 (1965): 446-448. Swift notes the importance of Lactantius continuing to respect the pagan tradition given his goal of swaying pagans to his views. 26 Lactantius, Divine Institutes I.11, 53. 18

PAGE 19

impossible for mortal to approach the immortal. 27 But the knowledge that humanity can gain of God stemmed primarily from the proper reco gnition of His oneness, his uniqueness. Hermes, as quoted by Lactantius, exclaims that there is but one religion of God, and that is not to be evil, which closely mirrors the precept from Pr overbs 8:13 that to fear Yahweh is to hate evil. 28 If refraining from evil was a common valu e between pagan philosophy and Christianity on which Lactantius could draw, then reveren ce for God was the methodology he believed could bind the two disparate groups together. In the en d, Lactantiuss ultimate goal for the Divine Institutes was an end to the Great Persecution by convincing educated pagans that they shared with Christians the same fundamental epistemol ogy and that the Christianity as taught by Christ was the path that pagan philosophy sought. Lactantius discusses at length the concept of reverence and pi ety in Book II of the Divine Institutes, making liberal and constant uses of Hermetic writings. Lactantius is wrestling with demons, like Firmicus Maternus and Augustine w ill after him, citing the same sections from Platos Symposium. His understanding of demons stems from the stories in the apocryphal Book of Enoch where fallen angels bege t earthly powers with mortal women. 29 These spirits masquerade as pagan gods, deceiving magicians into seeing things that do not exist and not seeing the things that do. 30 Both Firmicus Maternus and later Augustine will follow Lactantius in their assessments of the role of demons, making them steadily more dangerous to mankind as the century progresses. Lactanti us again quotes directly from He rmes when he explains that 27 Lactantius, Divine Institutes II.8, 134. 28 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum XII.23, 48, Proverbs 8:13 Quoted in Lactantius, Divine Institutes VI.25, 468. 29 As with Arius, Rabbinic commentary on the Book of Enoch is another avenue of exploration defining the shared culture examined here. 30 Lactantius, Divine Institutes II.16, 156. See also the discussion below on Firmicus Maternus and De Errore Ch. 26. Firmicus very clearly mirrors Lactantiuss judgment on demonic deception, as will Augustine. 19

PAGE 20

reverence is the knowledge of God. 31 Later, in Book V, he acknowledges justice as the greatest virtue and credits the source of jus tice to piety, or knowle dge of God, once again referencing Hermetic arguments from Book II. If it is piety to know God, and this is the highest form of this acquaintance that you may cultivate, certainly he does not know justice who does not hold to the religion of God. For how can he know that (justice) itself w ho is ignorant of where it comes to be?32 Lactantius credits Plato for understanding just ice, though he failed to overthrow the false worship of pagan gods; moreover, he claims that Socrates went to his death because he was unable to complete the process. Here Lactantiu s seems to admit the possibility that Socrates could have initiated Christianity without Christ. This possibility follows from Lactantiuss focus on Christ as a teacher, a fo cus that would be significantly diminished by the soteriological concepts at the heart of the Council of Nicaea and later highlighted by Firmicus Maternus. There are many references throughout the Corpus Hermeticum supporting these id eas of reverence, piety, and knowledge of God. For Hermes, the vice of the soul is ignorance but the virtue of the soul, by contrast, is knowledge; for one who knows is good and reverent and already divine.33 Hermes himself, after receiving his di vine understanding, goes out into the world proclaiming to mankind the beauty of reve rence and knowledge, sounding much like a missionary proselytizing.34 31 Lactantius, Divine Institutes II.15, 155 quoting from the Corpus Hermeticum X.4, 28. Reverence is knowledge of god, and one who has come to know god, fille d with all good things, has thoughts that are divine and not like those of the multitude. The longer section shows some of the exclusivity inherent in the Hermetic writings which Augustine will take issue with late r, supporting the more universal approach of a Christian Church. See also Copenhavers notes 151-152 for similar quotations from Ciceros On the Nature of the Gods whom Lactantius also cites positively. 32 Lactantius, Divine Institutes V.14, 363-364. 33 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum X.8-9, 32. 34 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum I.27, 6. 20

PAGE 21

Elizabeth Digeser argues that Lactantius us ed the Hermetica to defend against arguments made by Porphyry that Christianity was a new religion, and should theref ore be shunned. With the support of Hermes, Lactantius could show th at the Christian religion was the more ancient due to its close affinity to this fount of ancient wisdom which had informed Plato.35 A careful examination of the sources lends support to this conclusion but also reveal s a specific series of rhetorical arguments employed by L actantius in his defense. Lactan tius limited his selection of Hermetic quotations to broad issues concerning th e nature of God, the nature of humanity, and knowledge of God. These specific issues are current to both Ch ristian and pagan theological discussion. He was not simply arguing for the anti quity of Christian religi on in these appeals but insisting on their clear applicability to the issu es most important to the educated pagans and Christians of his day. Lactantiuss attempt to tap into the commonly held monotheistic beliefs represented by the Hermetic writings (and the cult of Theos Hypsistos ) must necessarily occupy a more central position than whether or not he is representative of other Christ ian theologians. His God was still close to humanity, ineffa ble and without name, but nonethel ess much closer to humankind than the increasingly esoteric philosophical monikers soon to be applied to him at upcoming Ecumenical Councils. Lactantius represented a view of Christ that would quickly become unacceptable and was not adopted at the Council of Nicaea. He argued instead for a God still approachable by humanity with Christ serving as the ideal model for human behavior, a teacher and a guide. Lactantius places th is lightgiving word into the tr adition of a teacher of wisdom, like Hermes himself or like Plotinus.36 Both took on the responsibi lity to show humanity how 35 Digeser, The Making of a Christian Empire 90. 36 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum I.26-27, 6-7. Poimandres joining the powers after his instruction to Hermes and then Hermes going out into the world to teach. 21

PAGE 22

best to achieve salvation and themselves had achieved a close relationship to God during their lives on earth. Christ was th erefore constituted midway be tween God and man (whence the Greeks call Him Mediator) to be able to le ad man to God, that is, to immortality.37 In his Divine Institutes then, Lactantius placed Christ between God and humanity and demonstrated a close connection between Christian and pagan belief but in the decades to come issues of fate and salvation would diminish the concept of Christ the Teacher in favor of Christ the Savior.38 After fleeing Nicomedia, Lactantius completed hi s work and ended his days in Trier at the court of the first Christian Emperor, Constantin e, as the personal tutor to the Emperors son, Crispus.39 Under the auspices of Constantine, La ctantius had suggested that shared beliefs amongst pagan and Christian would allow a compromi se. The pagan literary past need not be abrogated, but subsumed under a more comprehens ive interpretation of the divine nature as guided by Christ. However, even as Constantine consolidated his power by defeating his eastern rival, Licinius, to become the so le Christian ruler of the Empire controversy had erupted in the east. The syncretic beliefs put forth by Lactantius were also found in the theology of the deacon Arius. The controversy temporarily solved at the Council of Nicaea centered on the Arian proposition that Christ the Son was subordinate to God the Father and that there was when the Son was not.40 Like the second god found in the Herm etica or the Platonic demiurge, Arius placed his Logos at the pinnacle of the Creation but he was nonetheless still a member of the created order.41 Ariuss concept of an intermediary allowed for a bridge between the created 37 Lactantius, Divine Institutes IV.25, 308. 38 Digeser, The Making of a Christian Empire, 74-78. 39 Ogilvie, 3. 40 Henry Chadwick, The Church in Ancient Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 195-200. 41 History of the World Christian Movement, Vo lume I: Earliest Christianity to 1453 ed. Dale T. Irvin and Scott W. Sunquist (Maryknowll, New York: Orbis Books, 2004), 173-179. 22

PAGE 23

23 world and the divine where the Son of God shar ed in both natures. It was the Son who had changed and suffered on the cross, not the Father. Opposed to this view were the concepts of Irenaeus who claimed for redemption to be possible God himself must be the conduit.42 Some modern scholarship has proposed that Ariuss vi ew was, in fact, the more conservative and avoided the troubling questi on of how an immutable God could have suffered.43 But in the end the Alexandrian delegation to the Council won the day, finding that Arian belief had placed Jesus in the position of a secondary god, locating the key figure in Christian theology uncomfortably close to the demigods and heroes of pagan mythology.44 The phrase homoousios then entered the Creed, insisted upon by Constantine, to desc ribe the Father and S on as consisting of one being.45 This deliberately vague philosophical term was a departure from the common monotheistic substrate of belief shared by Lactan tius, Arius, the Theos Hypsistos cult, and the Hermetica.46 Another pagan converted to Christianity (by no means a theologian) demonstrates the effects of this new relationship between God a nd the Logos. As Christianity diverges more severely from the surrounding pagan belief syst em, the position of Hermes Trismegistus is diminished as well. 42 Chadwick, The Church in Ancient Society, 197. 43 Drake, 238. Drake cites a number of authors supporting this assertion. See the Conclusion for the theoretical support the Corpus lends to this idea. 44 Ibid., 239. 45 Chadwick, The Church in Ancient Society, 199. 46 Further examination of congruency between Arian and He rmetic beliefs will be the subject of a future chapter of a dissertation. Separating true Arian teaching from the polemic attacks against him will entail a different form of comparative scholarship than the direct quotations I am examining here. However, Arius is vital in any attempt to recover the substrate, the underlying environment of belief, which these four topics share and from which orthodox Christianity diverged.

PAGE 24

CHAPTER 3 FIRMICUS MATERNUS The Late Antique pagan aris tocrat, Firmicus Maternus, offers a unique glimpse of Christian belief during the reign of Constantine and his sons. Ten years after writing the Matheseos Libri VIII ( The Theory of Astrol ogy in Eight Books), the most complete extant work of astrology from this period, Firm icus converted to Ch ristianity and wrote a blistering antipagan treatise, the De errore profanarum religionem ( The Error of the Pagan Religions ). Like the Mathesis on astrology, De Errore provides more detail on act ual pagan practices in the mystery religions than any other work from Late Antiquity. In his transition from pagan to Christian, Firmicus maintained some pagan doctr ines while dispensing w ith others. Both of his major works reveal the shared Neoplatonic and Christian view of reality that is also present in the Corpus Hermeticum But some of Firmicuss belief s did change in relation to the Corpus requiring him to refute the possible benefits of dem onic interventions. It is here that elements of a crystallizing Christian orthodox doctrine can be seen in a decidedly unorthodox convert. Although the dates of his birt h and death are not known, th e dates of his works and location of his writing have been firmly established. Firmicus dedicates the Mathesis to Constantine the Most Great Pr inceps and his unconquered child ren, our lords and Caesars, indicating a writing no later than th e death of Constantine in 337ce.1 An educated Roman citizen of senatorial rank, Firmicus claimed Sic ily as his place of birth and residence.2 He acquired his 1 For Firmicus Maternus, see Ancient Astrology Theory and Practice trans. Jean Rhys Baum (Park Ridge, New Jersey: Noyes Press, 1975). All references to his astrological work will be referenced as follows Mathesis I.X.14, 30. Firmicus Maternus also discusses a solar eclipse that can be precisely dated to 334ce, providing an accepted authorship between 334-337ce. See also Firmicus Maternus, The Error of the Pagan Religions in Ancient Christian Writers: The Works of the Fathers in Translation trans. Clarence A. Forbes (New York: Newman Press, 1970), 3-5 for a full discussion of dating. All refere nces to this work will be referenced as De Errore followed by chapter and page numbers. 2 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis I.Proemium.4, 11. the geography of Sicily where I was born and where I make my home. 24

PAGE 25

education in the classical authors and rh etoric appropriate to a member of the vir clarissimus rank, including training in Greek, before practici ng law. As was common to the educated classes, he may have been an initiate of one or more of the mystery religions, particularly Mithraism.3 As a promise to his friend Mavortius, then governor of Campania, Firmicus gathered the astrological knowledge of the Egyptians and Babylonians into the Mathesis ; a project far larger than he expected, for which he rebuked himself after having committed to write it.4 The work is a series of t echnical treatises on as trology, providing instruction for casting and interpreting horoscopes. The eight books begin with a defens e of astrological prediction followed by detailed books describing the signs, planets, astrological hou ses and the technical interactions of these various elements. He also discusses the trai ning and virtues of the astrologer including modesty, uprightness, and so briety, with special warnings against the shameful love of money.5 The writings betray Firmicuss commitment to fatal determinism, which claimed that human beings were incapable of escaping the dictates of the stars, imparted at birth.6 However, Firmicus takes special care to warn against casting horoscopes of the Emperor since the Emperors fate is reserved to God alone.7 Although Firmicus does not allow for escape from this influence through Neoplatonic unificati on with the One, his determinism is mitigated by appeals to Socratic virtue. After his conve rsion a decade later, he opts for the redemptive mediation of Christ, expounded in the De Errore. Based on references from the Persian campaigns of Constans to the imperial decree agai nst pagan sacrifice, 346 ce is an accepted date 3 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Introduction, 6-7. 4 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis I.Proemium.6-7, 12. 5 Ibid., Mathesis II.30, 68. 6 Ibid., Mathesis I.Proemium, pp. 4. 7 Ibid., Mathesis II.30, 69. 25

PAGE 26

of authorship for the De Errore.8 In his new commitment to Ch ristianity, Firmicus takes an extreme stance against all pagan religious prac tices, going far beyond the growing set of laws curbing those practices, and advocating state-sp onsored elimination of the traditional cults. Where once Firmicus praised Porphyry in the Mathesis he now scorned and derided him for his belief in good demons, foreshadowing Augustines position a century later.9 The Pagan: The Theory of Astrology in Eight Books Establishing Firmicuss access to the Corpus are passages in both of his works, preand post-conversion, relating to his unde rstanding of the will of God. W ith language taken directly from the Hermetica, Firmicus demonstrates one particular element of the Greek philosophic tradition subsumed by Christianity. Corpus Hermeticum treatise X asserts that Gods activity is will, and his essence is to will all things to be.10 These same sentiments are found in the Neoplatonic thought of Plotinuss Enneads where Gods act of will and the coming-into-being of the substance of that act are simultaneous and indistinguishable.11 Plotinus goes further by claiming that the existence of all sensible things and their teleological reason for being are both produced at the one stroke.12 Firmicus shows this same understanding by quoting in both the Mathesis and De Errore not from Plotinus, but from a key passage in the Asclepius : 8 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Intro, 9. 9 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Intro, z4. 10 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum X.2, 30. Also X.3, But god the father is the good in that he wills all things to be. 11 For Plotinus, see The Enneads, trans. Stephen McKenna (London, Penguin Books: 1991) VIII.13-21. particularly end of XIII, 526. Plotinus (204ce-270ce) was the third-century philos opher credited with founding Neoplatonism. His works are transmitted with a short biography by his student Porphyry. All background information on him comes through Porphyry. His philosoph ical system is indebted to Socrates, Plato, and Numenius as well as Stoic and Peripatetic philosophy, incl uding the concept of a God consisting of three hypostases of the One, the Intellect, and the All-Soul. Plotinus is the main source for Iamblichus in addition to the Hermetica. 12 Plotinus, Enneads VIII.14, 527. 26

PAGE 27

Gods will is itself perfect achievement since willing and achievement are complete for him at one and the same moment of time. ( voluntas etenim dei ipsa summa est perfectio utpote cum voluisse et perfecisse uno eodemque temporis puncto compleat.)13 Unlike Lactantius, Firmicus limits his direct quota tion of the Hermetica to just a few passages, but the presence of this language in both treatises points not only to Firmicuss knowledge of the Asclepius but to the acceptance of this key conc ept within both a Christian and pagan framework, at least to the understa nding of a recent convert. In the case of the Nicene Creed, the term homoousios entered orthodox belief as a conscious import from Greek philosophy. In the case of the voluntas dei the concept is seamlessly shared by Neoplatonist, Hermetist, and Christian alike. While Books II through IV of the Mathesis describe the initial identification of horoscopes and begin the interpretiv e process, it is not until Book V that Firmicus delves into the true power of the signs. It is at this point that he must invoke divine protection to prevent the knowledge of astrology falling into the wrong hands, a nd he turns directly to Hermes to describe God. In preparation for discussing the signs of th e Zodiac, Firmicus first offers a prayer to the One God, acknowledging the Sole Governor and Chie f of all, Sole Emperor and Lord, to whom the entire force of the heavenly powers is subs ervient, whose Will is the essence of finished creation.14 He will later praise the voluntas dei in the Christian De Errore with a much more ominous tone towards the serpent and his cohorts. Quoting from Is aiah, Firmicus exclaims that God shall slay the great snake Satan for the Will of God is the substance of the completed work.15 The exact sense of the power and immediacy of divine will is maintained as Firmicus crosses the growing divide betw een Christian and pagan. As es tablished by Plotinus, and then 13 Copenhaver, Asclepius .8, 71. Here summa implies essence, principal matter, or substance. 14 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis .V.praefatio, 155. Cuius voluntas perfecti operis substantia est. Substantia is used similarly to summa as nature or substance. 15 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Ch. 26, 103. Voluntas dei perfecti operis substantia est. 27

PAGE 28

applied by Firmicus through the Asclepius to the Christian God, God s act of willing an effect and the coming-into-being of that effect are one and the same. Bringing the voluntas dei into his conception of Christ ianity from its Neoplatonic and Hermetic sources was acceptable, but there were some doctrines from the Corpus that disappear entirely in his transition from Mathesis to De Errore For instance, in the same prayer found in the praefatio of Book V of the Mathesis Firmicus conceptualized G od as Father of all and at the same time Mother, a common Neoplat onic construction also found in the Asclepius .16 In dialogue with his disciple Tat, Hermes acknowledge s that God is of both sexes, confirmed also in Corpus Hermeticum treatise I as androgynous and in Corpus Hermeticum treatise V as a creative will identified as both mother and father.17 In a similar opening prayer in the proemium of Book III, Firmicus praises God the Creator, copying nature, has made man in the image of the universe, not in the image of God.18 None of these descriptions about the nature of God are maintained in the De Errore. Like Lactantius before him, Firmicus praises Aesculapius and Hanubis for their teaching of the thema mundi the astrological birth chart of the universe upon which the fates of men depend, and it is to them Most Powerful Mercury (Hermes) entrusted the secret.19 At each point in his books when Firmicus takes the opportunity to praise or describe God, he incorporates either Hermetic quotation di rectly or ideas present in the Hermetica and 16 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis .V.praefatio, 156. 17 Copenhaver, Asclepius .21, 79. Corpus Hermeticum I.9, 2 and I.15, 3, Corpus Hermeticum V.7, 19. See also Copenhavers notes on androgyne, 103. 18 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis .III.proemium, 71. 19 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis .III.I.1, 71. Aesculapius = Asclepius, Hanubis = the Egyptian god Anubis. 28

PAGE 29

found in other Neoplatonic sources as well.20 Neither the praise for Hermes nor the creation myths of the Hermetica surviv e his Christian transformation. The Christian: The Error of the Pagan Religions Beyond the voluntas dei Firmicuss beliefs change ra dically after conversion. In De Errore the living entities that participated in the fatal determ inism of astrology and were worthy of praise in the Mathesis became either tools of God, emptied of meaning in the light of Christ, or vile enemies of God and the Christian commun ity. Returning again to the opening prayer of the Mathesis Book V, Firmicus praises the Sun in language familiar to the Hermetica. The Sun orders all things in the heaven s, provides the immortal soul in all living things, and wills the disposition of the fates.21 Within the Asclepius the Sun is a second god governing all things and shedding light on all that are in the world.22 Hermes further explains in Corpus Hermeticum treatise XVI exactly how the Sun governs the fate of humans. The Sun governs troops of demons, some good, some bad, who at the exact mo ment of birthtake possession of each of us as we come in to being and receive a soul.23 In this role, it is the Sun that drives the determinism of astrology and which Firmicus seeks to placate by asking forgiveness for revealing the secrets of prediction through horoscopes. Yet, after his conversion, the Sun has not only lost this preeminent position, but has only one true purpose. Rail ing against the mystery 20 The Proemium to Book VI contains a list of Gods creative accomplishments mirrori ng those of Book V, as does the Astrologers Oath in Book VII. The Astrologers Creed in Book VIII contains a brief remark on the soul being lost if given into vicious desires. 21 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis .V. praefatio, 156. 22 Copenhaver, Asclepius .29, 85. 23 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum XVI.14, 60. For Plato, the human soul is constructed by the gods beneath the One God and creator. It is through their failed understanding and individuality that the human soul becomes susceptible to the outside world and confused. Plato considers the soul a physical object consisting of rotating spheres that should be in harmony with each other according to specific ratios. For Plato, see Timaeus and Critias trans. Desmond Lee (London: Penguin Books, 1977), 59-61. 29

PAGE 30

religions, Firmicus has the Sun itself address its false worshippers, sayi ng I was created by God to usher in the day, and that alone is enough for me.24 Gone is any mention of fate or in a solar determinant for the immortal soul. Firmicus reduced the Sun to a s upporting role only, and a physical one at that, claiming that I frankly show myself as ju st what I am, and I want you to understand of me nothing else but what you see. Although earlier scholars are correct in observing that Firmicus did not directly attack the astrology of his pagan convictions, the removal of the Sun from its celestial position in determinism fundamentally degrades the strength of the stars in ruli ng the fate of human beings.25 Thorndike characte rized this rebuke of pagans by the Sun as evidence that he (Firmicu s) still regarded the stars as of immense importance in the administration of the universe. On the contrar y, Firmicus gives only a literary voice to the Sun. The Sun has lost its power to affect human lives because the intermediary role of celestial demons has been supplanted in his new Christian theology by the role of Christ. There is no need to attack astrology when the core dependency on the stars for governing fate has already been eliminated. Schol ars have also claimed that Firmic us is inconsistent even in his earlier belief in fatal determinism, citing his prayers to the gods in an attempt to resist the influence of the stars.26 But Firmicus himself cites Socrates as having overcome his base earthly impulses by the power of wisdom and virtue, which is also supported by Corpus Hermeticum treatise XVI.27 Demons twist and manipulate two parts of Platos tripartite soul, but the rational 24 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Ch. 8, 63. 25 Lynn Thorndike, A Roman Astrologer as a Historical Source: Julius Firmicus Maternus, in Classical Philology 8:4 (Oct., 1913): 419. Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Introduction, 19-20 and note 88, 135. 26 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis .I.VI.2, 20. Even Plotinus succumbed to the stars for Firmicus, Book I.VII.14-22, 22-23. 27 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis .I.VI.3-4, 20. Plato posited three parts of the soul located in three parts of the body. The emotions and feelings of the heart and the phy sical appetites of the belly were the parts susceptible to demons and stellar influences. The powers of reason and decision making located in th e head could be trained to 30

PAGE 31

part of the soul stands unmastered by the demons, suitable as a receptacle for god and Hermes calls this manipulative process Fate.28 Corpus Hermeticum treatise XII concurs that all people are subject to fate but that tho se that possess reasonare not aff ected as the others are. For the divine part of the human soul, nothing is impossibleneither setting a human soul above fate nor, if it happens that a soul is careless, settin g it beneath fate.29 However, unlike his incorporation of the voluntas dei in both the Mathesis and De Errore, as a Christian, Firmicus could no longer rely on prayers to the gods or a So cratic human virtue to escape the dictates of the stars. Instead, Firmicus replaced the rule of Fate with the innova tive rule of Christ Redeemer. The brunt of Firmicuss attack fell on the my stery religions. His at tack was ferocious and specific, betraying an intimate knowledge of ritual practices; perhaps the polemic of a recent convert assaulting his former cult cohorts as proof of his new faith.30 The sources of his classical education like Cicero, Ovid, and Livy ar e still reliable for th eir rhetorical skill.31 Bu where Firmicus could also accept certain attributes of the Neoplatonic god and transfer them to his Christian God, he could not accept the worshi p of figures he thought were at worst balef emissaries of the Devil and at best men inflated to godlike proportion. Like Lactantius, Firmicus employed euhemerism as a primary point of attac k. After this lengthy as sault on the failures of the mystery religions, Firmicus provides a Christian alternative to fate and death in two chapters t ul overcome these baser influences. Plato, Timaeus and Critias 16-17 for an introductory summary, 97-100 for Platos main discussion. 28 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum. XVI.15-16, 60-61. 29 Copenhaver, Corpus Hermeticum. XII.9, 45. 30 The fact that Firmicus does not attack a Hermetic cult is itself interesting. This may add some weight, ex nihilo to the theory that Hermetic doctrine never did reach the level of cult practice and worship, at least not in the time of Firmicus to be worthy of specific attack. 31 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Introduction, 22-25. 31

PAGE 32

on the triumph of Christ, repeating the developing Christian doctrine of r ecapitulation that would not become orthodox for centuries. For Firmicus after conversion, Christ became the one entity who had escaped the cycle of death. Supporting his exegesis through the use of Biblical quotations found most likely in Cyprian, Firmicus demonstrates the death, resurrection, and spiritual inheritance of Christ.32 The recapitulation doctrine that Firmicus asserts, discovered through his acquaintance with the wo rks of Irenaeus, is that Christ regained through self-sacrifice what Adam had lost through transgression.33 The immortality which the philosophers and the Hermetists sought had once been available to humanity, but by scorning Gods commands, this man [Adam] ensnared the human race in the aff liction of mortality and it is through renewed obedience that humans may ag ain attain this realm.34 The redemptive goal of Christ is to save mankind, to conquer death, to link the frailty of the human body with divine immortality.35 By 529ce and the Second Council of Orange, this doct rine would be an admitted part of orthodox belief, but in the mid-fourth centu ry it was a distinct break with a pagan past, and in the case of Firmicus, a supporting concept for an escape from death without resort to the training of the Hermetica or the trappings of the mystery religions.36 However, Firmicuss greatest departure follows closely his demotion of the Sun from astr ological entity to simple celestial light with far greater consequence for pagan worshippers. Although Firmicus may not have directly denigr ated his past astrol ogical beliefs, he took an entirely different, violently partisan view of the demons which interact ed with the human soul 32 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Ch. 24, 95-100. 33 Ibid., see note 470, 213. 34 Ibid., Ch. 25, 100-102. 35 Ibid., Ch 25, 101. 36 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Note on 470. 32

PAGE 33

as the operational forces of Fate. The demons of the Hermetica were not the post-Christian embodiments of evil. These are the of Platos Symposium divinities midway between gods and men, between mortal and immortal.37 For Plato, communicate between gods and men and are the sources of pr ophecy, spells, and enchantments.38 For Hermes, take on many roles and according to their nature can be good, evil, or a mixture of the two. They are airy spirits, existing between physical humanity and the spiritual gods, a form of entity from which humans originated and to which they return after death. ristian 39 But Firmicus no longer accepts either of these possibilities, instead relegating to their familiar role as Ch demons.40 The gods worshipped by pagans are in fact creations of the Devil for he devised those gods whom you worship.41 The temptation brought by the Serpent in the Garden, that you shall be as gods, is now an affront to Fi rmicuss Christian sensibility as opposed to a legitimate goal of Neoplatonic or Hermetic philosophy.42 And the purpose that demons serve is no longer one of possible support or even the transmi ssion of qualities to the soul in the sense of fatal astrological determinism. Instead, demons through the Devil boast that you help wretched men all that you may slay them by your cr uelty, deceive them by your persuasions, and overthrown them by your promises.43 These words will sound familiar when encountered again in the writings of Augustine a century later. Li ke Augustine, Firmicus derided Porphyry, but in 37 For Plato, see The Symposium: The Dialogues of Plato, vol. 2 trans. R. E. Allen (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1991 ) commentary, 48-49. 38 Plato, Symposium 202d-203a, 146. 39 Copenhaver, Asclepius .5, 69, Corpus Hermeticum .I.23, 5, Corpus Hermeticum .II.14, 11. 40 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore commentary, 14. 41 Ibid., Ch. 26, 103. 42 Ibid., Ch. 26, 102. 43 Ibid., Ch. 26, 103. 33

PAGE 34

this case, he turned on a teacher he had respected. Porphyry, who was praised in the Mathesis as our Porphyry, who supported the secret tran smission of astrological knowledge only amongst the elect, is attacked in De Errore as the defender of the cults enemy of God, foe of the truth, teacher of the arts of wickedness.44 During the short quarter-century from Lactan tius to Firmicus, Hermes Trismegistus was transformed from pagan prophet to polemical targ et, reflecting the needs of a growing Christian community seeking to define itself. As the pr ocess proceeded, certain el ements of Neoplatonic thought were imported (like the consubsta ntial Father and Son of the Nicene homoousios ), others were amicably maintained (like the voluntas dei ), still others (like the ) took on a new, insidious form. In the Hermetica, the hierar chy of being had placed demons midway between humanity and the Gods, ennobli ng them with a purpose, albeit ambiguous, of performing both good and evil deeds. But after th e defeat of the second god of Arius, Lactantius, and the Hermetica at Nicaea, Christianity had continued its assault deeper into this hierarchy, stripping the demons of any positive attributes. The Christian Firmicus accepted their new role and viciously attacked not pagan misunderstanding of the divine nature, but pagan practices and worship, recommending the full force of the state be applied in stamping out false religion. In fact, some of Firmicuss peculiar choice of wording appears in the Theodosian Code itself. The decree of 346ce under Constantius and Constans demands the closure of all temples in all cities so as to deny all abandoned me n the opportunity to commit sin.45 These abandoned men, perditi mentioned seven times in the De Errore, are to be struck down with the avenging sword according to the Code. The gladius vindex is also an element in the De Errore when 44 Firmicus Maternus, Mathesis .VII.1, 233, De Errore Ch 13.4, 72. 45 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore commentary, 14. Pharr, Theodosian Code XVI.10.4, 472. 34

PAGE 35

35 Firmicus quotes in his final chapter from Deut eronomy 13.6 that even a wife, brother, or son shall be killed for convincing others to serve other gods.46 Firmicus was able to abandon the interlocutors so vital to the determinism of astrology by depending fully on the redemptive power of Christ. But during this process, the distance between humanity and God had grown. It would remain for one of the Fathers of the Chur ch a century later to resolve the issue, again confronting the Corpus Hermeticum by showing that an entity at once fully human and fully divine could bridge the growing gap. 46 Firmicus Maternus, De Errore Ch. 29.1-2, 115. See Commentary, 17, note 561 on 226 and note 81 on 134135.

PAGE 36

CHAPTER 4 AUGUSTINE Already in some of his earliest theological writings, twenty years before he developed his full-fledged critique of the Hermetic Corpus in City of God Augustine began to formulate and express theological opinions about the ident ity and teachings of Hermes Trismegistus. Before his definitive encounter with Hermes on the grounds of mediation, he had two other occasions to address the pagan sage. In Contra Faustum written in 398ce, he disputes the Manichaean denial of the Old Testament.1 In the dialog, Faustus argues that Hermes can be used to persuade pagans to believe in Christianity whereas the Hebrew Old Testament cannot.2 His central argument for inclusion of the Hebrew Old Testament is that it contains many writings that carry the weight of ancient authority, bears directly on Christ, and can strengthen the presentation of the New Testament.3 In confronting the uses of pagan philosophy, Augustine incorporat es a typical set of pagan authorities, incl uding the Sibyls and Orpheus.4 By referencing Hermes and the other pagan writers, he follows a discursive style of pagan citation where Chri stians could find some use for pagan ideas. He notes that Hermes may be useful for the refuta tion of pagan error, but cannot lead us to believe. Augustine d ealt with the use of pagan authors in De Doctrina Christiana, first written between 395ce and 397ce, but only completed in 426ce.5 He explains that we were not wrong to learn the alphabet just because they say that the god Mercury was its 1 For Augustine, see St. Augustin: the Writings against the Manichaeans and against the Donatists in Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers XIII, ed. Philip Schaff and Henry Wace (Peabody, Massachusetts: Hendrickson Publishers, 1994). All English translations are from this edition. References to Augustines Contra Faustum are taken from this edition and will be referenced as Contra Faustum with book, section, and page numbers. 2 Augustine, Contra Faustum.XIII.1. 3 Ibid, XIII.8. 4 Lactantius also follows this pattern, usually quoting from all three sources as foreshadowing Christianity. See Divine Institutes .IV.6, 255-257 for examples of quotations from multiple Sibyls and Hermes. 5 For Augustine, see De Doctrina Christiana trans. R. P. H. Green (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995 ), xi-xiii. All English translations are from this edition. 36

PAGE 37

patron, even from those who worship in the form of stones.6 But even in this early encounter, he notes many flaws in Hermes, which will later l ead him to the polemic style of pagan citation found in City of God Even though they may have spoken of the Christian God, they lead their people to worship idols and demons. The value of their prediction is like the confession of devils against the proclamation of angels.7 In both of these cases, Augustine is indirectly addressing Hermes, but already holds a negative view of the figure which will become more pessimistic through the development of his theology of mediation. Early Writings In these writings, as in his later theological treatises, Augustine illustrates the development of Christian orthodoxy after the Council of Ni caea by paying particular attention to the Christological definitions that would be decide d at Ephesus a year after his death. His early views on Hermes in the Contra Faustum serve a mostly conventional view of pagan authors as possible support for Christian ar gument. He also supported the cautious inclusion of Hermetic knowledge in De Doctrina Christiana. By the time he writes City of God however, he has found a much more appropriate use for Hermes. At th e heart of his understanding of Christ is the theology of mediation. Developed in both the Confessions and much more fully in City of God, Augustine finds in the wholly human and wholly divine nature of Christ the one and only possibility of bridging what he understood to be an infinite divide between human beings and God. Engaging the pagan author Apuleius on his own terms, Augustin e constructs logical fallacies to discredit the pagan doctrine of demonic mediation. He works from this proof when attacking pagan practices, particularly the gods made by men and the deception of Hermes, 6 Ibid, II.18, 91. 7 Augustine, Contra Faustum, XIII.15. 37

PAGE 38

both found in the Latin Asclepius of the Corpus Hermeticum In confronting the Corpus Augustine also addresses the universal appeal of th e Christian message and the cult of the saints. Yet foundational to his developed theo logical objections to the Hermetic Corpus would be his understanding of the distinctive mediating role of Christ. Augustine first set down his t houghts on mediation in his Confessions, written nearly twenty years after his conversion in Milan, before comparing the positive results of this doctrine against the negative results of pa gan demonic mediation through the Corpus The first nine books of the Confessions form an autobiography of his early years and eventual conversion to Catholic Christianity.8 Beyond the autobiographical account of the young man, the latter four books are devoted to the issues of philosophy and theology current to Augustine the bishop. Book X, devoted to his concept of memory, c ontains his explanation of how to come to knowledge of God as well as the barriers to this process. Beginning w ith the desire to know God, so as to better know himself, Augustine exa lts the faculties of memory as a hypothetical tool to know God, beginning from the premise that love of God is a certainty, not a feeling.9 He first searches the physical world fo r God but finds the mind superior.10 After introducing concepts like number and logic, none of whic h come directly from sense perception, he concludes, echoing Platos con cept of Forms existing independ ent of perceived reality and accessible to the soul before birth, that memory is an act of recollection of concepts already 8 For Augustine, see Confessions trans. Henry Chadwick (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 19 91), xi-xxiii. All English translations are from this edition. See Peter Brown, Augustine of Hippo (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2000), 174-175, for chronological tables and the dating of Augustines writings. 9 Augustine, Confessions .X.5, 85. 10 Ibid, X.6, 183-184. 38

PAGE 39

present in the mind.11 He then explores his own emotions and the mind itself, but God still remains outside all these faculties.12 Next, Augustine begins to a ddress the source of these ideas recalled by memory. His discussion focuses on understanding the idea of happiness present in all human beings and he asks the crucial question : But how have they known about it so as to want it?13 He argues that regardless of the individual definition of happiness, all men seek this and share in the understanding of what happiness is, even thos e laboring under the self-deception that something other than God can fulfill this de sire. Finally, he concludes that God is a transcendent being outside the world yet recognized by all. Where then did I find you so that I could learn of you if not in th e fact that you transcend me?14 Augustines search for God yields no success, leading him to propose Gods true ina ccessibility and the necessity for a particular kind of connection between God and humanity. Augustine, therefore, conceives a distant G od, found neither in the physical world nor in the recesses of memory. He places God outside all of these experiences as the abiding light by which I investigated these matte rs to discover whether they existed, what they were, and what value should be attached to them.15 He has constructed his vision of God as informing all of reality, perceived throug h the senses as well as through the mind, yet the faculties available to humanity, even in their infinite capacity for im agination, are not enough to reach God. He asks 11 Ibid, X.10, 189. The ideas signified by those sounds I have not touched by sense-perception, not have I seen them independently of my mindSo they were there even before I had learnt them, but were not in my memorythe answer must be that th ey were already in the memory. 12 Ibid, X.25, 201. just as you are not a bodily image no r the emotional feeling of a living person such as we experience when glad or sad, or when we desire, fear, remember, forget, and an ything of that kind, so also you are not the mind itself. 13 Ibid, X.20, 196. 14 Ibid, X.26, 201. 15 Ibid, X.40, 218. 39

PAGE 40

Who could be found to reconcile me to you?16 This question leads him to the doctrine of Christ as the only mediator to bri dge this gap. Both here in the Confessions and later in Book VIII of City of God Augustine directly engages pagan author s on the issue of bridging the infinite divide between created and Creator showing that only one who participates fully in both realms can act as mediator between the two. The attack on paganism in the Confessions is very general, almost an aside used to strengthen an already successful argument about the nature of God and humanity. Given the nature of the God Augustine has expounded and the failure of human faculties to reach such a God, he finds it easy to ask leading questions of his pagan opponents: Was I to beg the help of angels? What prayer should I use? What sacred rites? These a nd other rhetorical questions are used to illustrate the folly of earthly intervention in approachi ng God. As to why pagans would believe such things, he credits the illusions of the devil: Thr ough an affinity in heart they attracted to themselves as associates and allies of their pride the powers of the air who deluded them with magical powers.17 Augustine will deal with both the illusions of the demons and how they might be attracted when dealing with the Latin Asclepius and those men who make gods, but the essential doctrine of Christ as medi ator will be the basis for all of the vehemence and scorn Augustine pours on those who worship them in the first place. City of God Beginning in 413ce, the Bishop of Hippo wrote City of God over the course of nearly fifteen years, with books I-XIV finished by 418ce and the final eight books not complete until 16 Ibid, X.42, 218. 17 Augustines reference to an affin ity of heart echoes his argument in De Doctrina Christiana that those who associate with demons have established a special set of agreed upon signs for communication. It is this affinity that allows the demons to deceive each person in a unique manner. See Augustine, De Doctrina Christiana II.24, 101. 40

PAGE 41

426ce.18 Augustine directly engages with pagan ph ilosophers including Porphyry and Plotinus, taking particular interest in th e works of Apuleius and Hermes Trismegistus. His conception of mediation is very similar in Confessions and City of God even to the point of asking almost identical rhetorical questions a bout prayers and rites, this time directly to the pagan author Apuleius.19 What changes in City of God is that the theologian develops a strong, logically constructed argument proving that the gods and demons of pagan philosophy are evil and the enemies of humanity, inherently d eceptive and therefore incapable of mediati ng with God. Then he confronts what he considers active examples of pagan worship, using both his proof of the evil of demons and the lamented prophecies of Trismegistus to show the emptiness of all pagan religion. Augustine uses the philosophical implications of Apuleius to attack the practices seen in the Asclepius Apuleius was a fellow African whose writings from 150ce still circulated by Augustines period. Known to modern readers through his novel Metamorphoses (or The Golden Ass), Apuleius constructed his own philosophy of mediation in De Deo Socratis ( The God of Socrates ), and Augustine deals almost exclusively with this work.20 Apuleius discusses the personal demon that accompanied Socrates and in the process assigned at tributes to gods and demons. He also supports the Platonic concept that no god has any dealings with men and therefore proposes demons as th e intermediary between the two.21 In answer to Huninks 18 For Augustine, see The City of God against the Pagans Vol. III, Books VIII-XI, Lo eb Classical Library, trans. David Wiesen (Cambridge: Harvard Univer sity Press, 1968), lxxviii-lxxxii. All English translations are from this edition. 19 Ibid., VIII.19, 89. Now, I ask, what kind of prayers of men does he suppose are carried to the good gods by demons magical prayers or legitima te? as compared to Augustine, Confessions X.42, 218. 20 For Apuleius, see Apuleius: Rhetorical Works ed. Stephen Harrison, John Hilton, and Vincent Hunink (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001 ) for a critical edition and translation of De Deo Socratis 21 Augustine, City of God VIII.18, 83. 41

PAGE 42

question as to why Augustine spends so much ti me on this text, he takes the statements of Apuleius (and Plato) as starting points for a generalized pagan view of the universe, then creates a series of logical arguments to discredit demons and demonstr ate their inability to act as intermediaries, leading to the alternative mediator he has in mind.22 In Book VIII, his first proof will demonstrate that demons are inherently evil, and later in Book IX he will show that there are no good demons. Acknowledging Plato as an authoritative figure in whom both pa gans and Christians could find merit, Augustine focuses on the expulsion of poets from the ideal city Plato proposes in The Republic Plato expels the poets for outrages agai nst the gods and corruption of the citizenry; however the gods themselves demanded stage plays and the praises of these same poets as worship.23 He questions what sort of gods woul d require what both Pl ato and Christians considered destructive, base, and wicked. A ugustine reviews the three forms of being of the Platonists, gods, demons, and human ity, and the five attributes that distinguish them, particularly the demons. Their species is animal, just as hum ans are terrestrial animals and gods are ethereal animals. All three share a rational mind, disti nguishing them from other, lower animals. Demons share their immortal bodies, uniquely com posed of air, with the gods, but share the passionate soul of men and, like men, share the wretchedness inherent in a soul moved by the disturbances of the passions.24 Gods, aloof from these passions, blessedly happy, never mixing with men, and defined by Plato as all good, cannot be the target of this base form of worship. Augustine first extrapolates that demons have de manded this worship and demons are the beings that Plato has offended by expelling the poets, not the good gods. Neither Apuleius nor Plato 22 Hunink, Apuleius, 89. 23 Augustine, City of God VIII.13, 59-61. 24 Ibid, VIII.16, 73-77. 42

PAGE 43

directly implicates demons in this expulsion. Augustines single logical leap to the conclusion that demons were the beings Plato was actually combating sets up a whole series of logically derived results about thei r nature that serve the remainder of his argument against pagan demonic mediation. Next, he concludes from Apuleius th at these beings between gods and humanity are said to convey to the gods the prayers of men and then bring back to men favorable answers to their requests.25 He then asks the question, if the demons are intermediaries, what was communicated to the good gods by the wretched de mons about Platos expulsion of the poets? Following an Aristotelian proof, Augustine succeeds in defining a set of terms which leads to the conclusion that demons are neither proper objects of worship, nor can they fulfill the role of intermediary. The demons must either tell the go ds the truth about Plato, implicating themselves in the wickedness of the poets, or they must conceal their own nature, or they must lie to the gods.26 Augustine succeeds at his initial task and then examines demons in practice through the Corpus Hermeticum particularly the Asclepius .27 The Asclepius is the Latin translation of the earlier Gr eek text referred to by Lactantius as the Perfect Discourse Probably translated in the four th century, the Latin version was unavailable to Lactantius but Augustine quotes directly and extensively from the text.28 Hermes Trismegistus addresses his discip le Asclepius, ranging over a wide variety of topics including the 25 Ibid, VIII.18, 83. 26 Ibid, VIII.21, 97-101. 27 The Asclepius was transmitted through a number of manuscr ipts also containing Apuleiuss works, leading to past arguments that Apuleius was its author. Those argum ents had ended, until recently, with the conclusion that Apuleius was not its author. See Vincent Hunink, Apuleius and the Asclepius, 288-308 for an alternative view reattributing the Asclepius to Apuleius. Mariateresa Sco tti provides a response in The Asclepius: Thoughts on a Re-Opened Debate, in Vigiliae Christianae 54:4 (2000): 396-416. See also Copenhaver, 214 for notes on translations of the Asclepius and on the attribution to Apuleius as groundless. 28 Fowden, 198. Note also that Lactantius explains that he has translated the Perfect Discourse directly from the Greek for his own use. The Epitome of the Divine Institutes Preface, Chapter 42. 43

PAGE 44

soul, the One god and other gods created by him, and the structure of the universe. Augustine finds in the text an opportunity to demonstrate the results of fraternizing with the malevolent spirits he has been discussing. He does not conc ern himself with whether or not he is dealing with actual Hermetic practices, r ecognizing that the most offensive aspect of this direct opposite to true religion occurred in some deep past.29 In City of God Augustine first attacks the Herme tic art of making gods. Hermes claimed that his ancestors had not only discovered the divine nature but had figured out how to create this nature as well. Using this art, de mons were called down into the statues of the great temples, and those statues ensouled and cons cious performed great deeds, prophecy, and cures.30 Hermes credits his gods that render loving kindness and give help by other means, but Augustine only finds in these mir acles more evidence of demonic deceit.31 As in his treatment of De Deo Socratis, he carefully chooses the passag es that support his theological position. Again, from previous proof, he shows that demons are either making pretense of benefiting their worshippers, to bring them to greater vice, or they are doing evil without disguise, such as those gods that require sacrifice for appeasement of anger. A passage in the Asclepius further reflects his argument regarding demons moved by the passions, just like men, in that anger comes easily to earthly and material gods because humans have made and 29 There is ongoing scholarly discussion for and agains t calling Hermeticism a religion. Grese sees Corpus Hermeticum XIII not as a liturgy but as supportive reading for cult members that have already been transformed by a Hermetic ceremony, Grese, 200-202; Fo wden sees the Hermetica describing a post-cultic phase of spiritual development, amenable to many of the practitioners of Late Antique paganism and mystery religions, Fowden, 146150; Quispel posits a true secret society based in Alexa ndria complete with rites and sacraments, Giles Quispel, The Asclepius: From the Hermetic Lodge in Alexan dria to the Greek Eucharis t and the Roman Mass, in Gnosis and Hermeticism: From Antiquity to Modern Times ed. Roelf van den Broek and Wouter J. Hanegraff (New York: State University of New York Press, 1998) 69-77. 30 Copenhaver, Asclepius 81-90. 31 Ibid, 90-91. 44

PAGE 45

assembled them from both natures.32 Augustine concedes that A puleius and Hermes disagree as to whether demons are mediators, but he brings to the Corpus the idea that all pagan interaction occurs with these sa me demons, finally concluding th at the demons of Hermes had no power in the world beyond that permitted them by God. t o s logy.35 33 The tenor of the entire argumen reflects Augustines contrast between the prope r worship of a loving Christ capable of intercession on behalf of human be ings as over against the false worship of demons that have n intercessory power and are bent only on deception.34 Bringing Augustines criticism of Apuleiu back into context as a method to crit ique the pagan practices found in the Asclepius also helps to explain why he avoided any of the positive re sults to be found in Apuleiuss theo The second part of Augustines attack deals with the ultimate results of demonic deception. In the same apocalyptic prophecy about an end to the ancient religion of Egypt that Lactantius had also dealt with, Hermes explains that his ancient ancestors made mistakes in their worship of the gods and as a result later invent ed the art of making their own gods.36 He goes on to explain that all Egyptian efforts towards worship will have been in vain, divinity will return from earth 32 Ibid, 90. 33 Augustine, City of God VIII.24, 125. 34 William E. Klingshirn, Divination and the Discp lines of Knowledge accord ing to Augustine, in Augustine and the Disciplines: From Cassiciacum to Confessions ed. Karla Pollmann and Mark Vessey (Oxford University Press, 2005), 137-140. Klingshirn discusses the centrality of Augustines mediation doctrine in regards to his view towards divination. The same distant God that necessitates a very special mediator also demonstrates why demonic access to foreknowledge can never be complete. 35 Hunink, Augustines Polemic against Apuleius 95. One cannot help wonder ing why Augustine reacts in so strong a manner, and why he simply omits the positive aspect s of Apuleius' theory of demons. It remains strange to see how an acute reader such as Augustine could misrepre sent his views, in spite of their common background as Africans. The point of Augustines attack is not to do justice to Apuleius, but to conflate Apuleius and Hermes to show the failure of pagan philosophy and practice. 36 Both Augustine and Lactantius had access to a prophecy describing a cleansing flood, fire, and pestilence, but substantial additional information is added afte r Lactantiuss translation. See Lactantius, Divine Institutes .VII.18, 520 for the prophecy available to Lactantius. 45

PAGE 46

to heaven, and Egypt will be abandoned.37 Hermes laments the denigration of the glorious construction of the world, a seri es of inversions in the role s of the mad for the wise, the scoundrel for the decent person, and the capital penalty for those w ho continue to reverence the gods.38 The Latin in the statement regarding the errors of the Egyptians is actually a mistranslation of the original Greek and Augusti ne interprets it in a purely negative light for Hermes. 39 He takes this statement to indicate that the Egyptians had long ago been exposed to the ideas of proper religion and as a result of thei r errors veered from the true religion into the mistake of worshipping idols crea ted through this new art. Unlike Lactantius and earlier authors, Augustine no longer focuses either on Hermes foreknowledge of Chri st or on his supportive arguments for a Christian God, instead finding an cient demonic deceptions and the failures they engender in Hermes. Deceived by the demons into lamenting the loss of a false religion, he failed to see Christianity, yet the power of God has forced him to admit these errors for later Christians to see and understand. If even an authority of such renown could be deceived by demons and yet, through the grace of the Christian God, be made to reveal these ancient errors, then the true religion and right belief has overcome the false. Augustine even provides an 37 Copenhaver, Asclepius 81. 38 The section of the prophecy that August ine deals with here was added to the Asclepius after the time of Lactantius. These views reflect a distinct fear of Christia n practices, including ascetics with a more negative view of the world. For a discussion of the dates of these additions, see Copenhaver, 239. Pierre Chuvin, A Chronicle of the Last Pagans trans. B. A. Archer (Cambridge : Harvard University Pr ess, 1990), 67-68, places the prophecy in the context of Alexandria, par ticularly the destruction of the Serapeum in 391. 39 Quoniam ergo proavi nostri multum errabant circa deorum rationem increduli et non animaduertentes ad cultum religionemque divinam: invenerunt artem qua efficerent deos (Therefore, since our remote ancestors erred concerning the doctrine of the gods, unbelieving and not attending to the form of worship and sacred reverence, they invented an art by which they could make gods), Augustine, City of God VIII.24, 114-116, my translation. Augustines explanation that Hermes has erred and then been forced by God to admit it is an attempt to explain a mistranslation of the Greek (when or after) to the Latin quoniam (since or because) Scott argues that Augustine may have been puzzled by this problem. However, I believe that Augustines solution agrees perfectly both with his proof of demons as deceivers and God as all powerful. See Walter Scott, Hermetica: The Ancient Greek and Latin Writings Which Contain Religious or Philosophic Teachings Ascribed to Hermes Trismegistus (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924-1936), Vol. IV, 183 for a discussion. Also see Copenhaver, Asclepius 90 for a translation from the Greek. 46

PAGE 47

apology for Hermes, maintaining to some extent his ancient reputation, by claiming it was the demons themselves that found expression in Hermes words.40 In a third objection, Augustine contrasts the universal Christ ian church with the elitist attitude present not only in the Asclepius but also found in Gnostic teachings.41 The surviving Hermetic works are classified as optimistic or pessimistic based on whether the world is seen as evil, similar to Gnostic views of the created universe.42 Even though the Asclepius is certainly optimistic both on the world and human itys unique position in it, the human goal of attaining divinity is only for the few.43 Once again, Augustine finds in these gods fashioned by men for a man of that kind, not for every man.44 The kinds of men that he is focused on a those, like Hermes, deceived in the distant past by the wiles of the demons, and maintaining those beliefs even in th e face of their own predic tions about the end of their religion. He enters into his final point, defending the cult of the sa ints. This point also stems from the Hermetic tradition of an end to religion in Egypt. Hermes predicts that Egypt w ill be filled completely with tombs and corpses, interpreted as an allusion to Christian practice as a form of re 40 Augustine, City of God VIII.26, 139 and VIII.24, 119. 41 See Irvin & Sunquist, 87-90 and 115-128 for brief notes on Gnostic secret knowledge only available to the elite. Although some of the topics dealt with by both Gnosticism and the Corpus Hermeticum are similar, Fowden credits this not to direct sharing but a general cultural mi lieu and shared systems of thought regarding divinity, the soul, and matter, see Fowden, Egyptian Hermes 113-155. 42 Differing views of the world present in the Corpus has led to much discussion in scholarship. Some treatises, labeled pessimistic view the world as an evil constructio n from which the soul must escape (similar to a Gnostic viewpoint), while others labeled optimistic view the world as the construction of a good god meant to instruct humanity. Fowden has argued that the two perspectives are consistent if viewed as a continuum along which an initiate travels. Optimistic treatises are therefore early in this process, using the world as a guide. Pessimistic treatises are for further on in the process of spiritual en lightenment, when the world is seen as holding the initiate back. See Fowden, Egyptian Hermes 97-102; Copenhaver, xxxix. 43 Copenhaver, Asclepius 79. Not all humans, but only the few who have the mind to contain so great a bounty, 77. 44 Augustine, City of God VIII.24, 127. 47

PAGE 48

48 worshipping the dead.45 Augustine gives a straightforward ac count of what Christians are doing regarding their saints. Saints are examples to be emulated, not gods to be worshipped. Banquets and offerings at memorials (which is not the prac tice of the better-instruct ed) are not sacrifices, but food is taken to the martyrs to be sanctified and then distributed to th e poor, for sacrifice is a rite that belongs to the service of one God alone.46 Augustines Christianity is one no longer acc epting of alternate pagan views. Never denying the reality of demons, or their power, he embraces a Christian world view where a distant God is only reached through Christ, and ancient religions have devolved into collusion with demons which have no positive traits whatsoev er. Not only is this path the only path, but unlike pagan hopes for divine transcendence, Christianity is open to ev eryone, not just to the spiritual or philosophic elite. As for a new Christ ian cult of the dead, A ugustine clarifies that the saints are not gods, nor are they worshipped as su ch. The real core of his argument concerns Apuleius and demons, but once his proof is available, the Corpus provides him with real-world examples to demonstrate the fundamental failure of pagan practices a nd a narrower spectrum of legitimate Christian belief. 45 Copenhaver, Asclepius 81. 46 Augustine, City of God VIII.27, 143.

PAGE 49

CHAPTER 5 CONCLUSION If, according to Boyarin, orthodoxyfunctions as a category to make and mark the border between Christianity and its proximate other re ligions then a full explanation of this border-formation process must include not only the separation of Christianity from Judaism, but Christianity from paganism as well.1 The Corpus Hermeticum can be used to define this second front in the battle of Christian iden tity formation based on the responses of a succession of authors and their changing perspectives over time. Whether real or imaginary, Hermes and his teachings in the Corpus Hermeticum (selectively appropriated or discredited within the works of Late Antique Christian au thors) demonstrates the shrinking boundaries of orthodox Christian theology. References to the Corpus show that this b oundary has moved ove time. Lactantius found in Hermes a kindred spirit with shared conceptions of the divine and a forceful argument for the merging of common Ch ristian and monotheistic pagan concepts which were permeating the eastern Empire immediately preceding the conversion of Constantine. But one effect of the Council of Nicaea was that Ch ristians could no longer accept the idea of a Savior who was at all similar to the gods and hero es of the pagan past. Shortly after, Firmicus Maternus showed that the re demptive qualities of the pagan had been subsumed by th redemptive Christ. Where Lactantius may quot e Hermes for his support, Augustine from th outset, in Contra Faustum is uncomfortable relying on the E gyptian; in fact he even wonders if there ever was such a person. r e e 2 For Augustine, Hermes now lie s almost wholly outside this 1 Boyarin, 206. In conversation with Dr. Boyarin on a visit to the University of Florida, in relation to Border Lines, he expressed regret that too much of the rest of the world (had been) left out, particularly paganism. It was this statement more than any other that helped place a conceptual framewo rk around this thesis. 2 Augustine, Contra Faustum, XIII.15. The final proof for Augustines suspicion would not come until the Renaissance when Isaac Casaubon in 1620, in the new tradition of Italian philology, examined the documents and showed the Greek language and place names were from the secondand third-centur y, not Mosaic antiquity. 49

PAGE 50

boundary. It is not until City of God that Augustine explains the ba sis of this exclusion through the development of his distin ctive theology of mediation. Following Irenaeus, Augustine definitively showed that the Christ of Arius and the demons of the pagans, both midway betw God and humanity, were insufficient to meet the needs of redemption. Brought about by the narrowing of Christian boundaries, the process w ould continue with Cyril of Alexandrias malicious delight in quoting Hermes during his attack on Julians Contra Galilaeos. een t of how orthodoxy develops.4 3 The continued examination of these changing refere nces to Hermes through other authors, both Christian and pagan, not only helps to define the evolution of the core Christian concepts that form orthodox belief, but places this process into the larger contex The Corpus and Religion Moving beyond the quotations of Herm es found in Christian writers, the Corpus reveals broader theoretical aspects regarding the forma tion of religion in general and heresy in particular. Responses to the Corpus provide concrete, supportive ex amples for the sociological examination of heresy. Jacques Berlinerblau defines three methodological axioms for the study of heresy, each of which is reflected in this examination. His first observation is that the relationship between heresy and orthodoxy is dynamic in nature. Both Lactantius and Firmicus demonstrate how orthodoxies grappl e with, and eventually incorporate, deviant beliefs into their theoretical frame of reference, so as to neutralize them.5 Initially, as a member of the orthodox, Lactantius attempts to incorporate the second go d of the Hermetica into Christianity. Although 3 Fowden, Egyptian Hermes 180-182. See Fowdens notes these pages for further reference to Cyril. 4 As has been outlined in previous footnotes, tracing th e lineage of pagan uses of Hermes in a dissertation will follow the line of Plotinus through Porphyry, who figures so prominently in the Christian authors discussed here, through Iamblichus and on to Julians failed attempt at a pagan revival. 5 J. Berlinerblau, "Toward a Sociology of Heresy, Orthodoxy, and Doxa," in History of Religions 40:4 (May, 2001): 332. 50

PAGE 51

conceptually acceptable to Arius, this definition does not build sufficient distance between pagan and Christian. The conflict with Arius and the changes made at Nicaea leads to Berlinerblaus second axiom that heresy requires a political organization to define it.6 The conversion of Constantine and the political reorganization flowing from this event may be a basis for understanding the politics of heresy, but the co nversion of Firmicus Maternus focuses on the larger issues of the applicati on of symbolic power in defining belief, and creating borders. Firmicus is at the center of s ymbolic struggles over the power to produce and to impose the legitimate vision of the world.7 Christians like Firmicus have changed their role from conciliators to eliminators, not only of pagan rights and sacred places but of the pagan hold on defining reality. The place of demons, the Sun, and the operation of Fate are distinct pagan cognitive structures eliminated in favor of Christ the Savior.8 Stripping the pagan belief system of its most powerful operatives is a step in the process of the new Chri stian group asserting is political power, its right to define itself and to reshape the intellectual world around it. The Corpus and Heresy Firmicuss role also points to Berlinerblaus final axiom that the heretic exists as a structural insider. Berlinerblau asks what specif ic criteria define the here tic as an insider; is it shared beliefs and values, membership in an el ite group, or a common disc ursive universe which the heretic then upsets?9 As Christianity built stronger borders between Christian and nonChristian, I propose that Firmicus Maternus be s een not merely as a polemical, new convert to Christianity, but as a pagan he retic. Bringing with him a deep knowledge of pagan practice and 6 Ibid., 332-335. 7 Pierre Bourdieu, Social Space and Symbolic Power, in Sociological Theory 7:1 (Spring, 1989): 20. 8 Ibid., 18. 9 Berlinerblau, 334-335. 51

PAGE 52

ritual, Firmicus turns viciously against his former co-practitioners. Key to forming the border between Christian and pagan, Christian legislatio n and efforts towards self-definition thrust upon pagans the need to see themselves as a group, perhap s for the first time. It is from this group, as defined by Christians, that heretics like Firm icus emerged. Boyarin employs the concept of Jewish response to explain an emergent Judaism as well; that only in its successful response to Christian attempts to label it a religion di d Rabbinic Judaism itself come into existence.10 Here also is tacit acknowledgem ent of Bourdieus assertion that sy mbolic power is actually the power to define groups. Evidence that pagans may have begun to see themselves as such a group is found in Julians attempt to use Iamblichus (and his dependence on Hermes) in defining a set of practices and beliefs, a doctrine, to oppose the Galileans. If Rabbinic Judaism succeeded in mounting an intellectual defense against Christia nity by rejecting and refusing the Christian definition of a religion, understood as a system of beliefs and practices to which one adheres voluntarily, then paganism failed.11 Firmicus is then fully an insider of this defined group which Christianity labels as opposing. He sh ares the same discursive framework as his Neoplatonic cohorts and falls into the category of intellectuals who dissent from the very orthodoxy to which they once belonged.12 The references to the Corpus Hermeticum used here helps frame the shared beliefs and values that allo w Firmicus to move from one group to another. The intellectual activity he once pe rformed in pagan discourse included articulating the role of divine intermediaries in the opera tion of Fate, which makes his reve rsal on the role of the Sun in De Errore so striking after his conversion. The role of Christ as the only mediator between God 10 Boyarin, 218-220. 11 Ibid., 224. 12 Berlinerblau, 340. 52

PAGE 53

and humanity forms the basis for attacks on paganism in all three authors, helping to form the border between pagan and Christian. The Corpus and Doxa Finally, the uses of Corpus Hermeticum help to reveal the intellectual landscape or substrate of Late Antiqu ity. Bourdieu identified doxa as the unthought assumptions and fundamental beliefs which do not even need to affirm themselves.13 Similarly, he refers to habitus as the mental stru cture through which (one) apprehe nd(s) the social world which allows members of a society to perceive the world as natural and to accept it much more readily than one might imagine.14 It is no coincidence that th ese Christian authors chose the Corpus Hermeticum first for incorporation and only later for attack. It is the Corpus Hermeticum that presents the existent intellectual world of Late Antiquity from which Christianity must distinguish itself. Additional work on Arian doctrine, the accusations against Eusebius of Caesarea of Hermetic influence, and the works of Philo of Alexandria wi ll lend further support to this supposition.15 Berlinerblau proposes a number of que stions that further research on the Corpus in Late Antiquity may serve to answer. What is the unquestioned and unified cultural tradition that binds together these adversaries ? In this case, the adversaries are the newly forming orthodox Christians and their Arian/pa gan contemporaries. He also asks if doxic commonalities exist only among (antagonistic) coreligionists.16 The Corpus Hermeticum answers this question with a re sounding negative. The creation of orthodox Christian belief is 13 Ibid., 346. 14 Ibid., 18. 15 Philo of Alexandria is another author that figures prominently in discussions of a second god. Whether there is direct contact between Philo and the Hermetica requires further research. See Ch. 5 of Boyarin, Border Lines 112-127 for a complete discussion of Philo and The Jewish Life of the Logos. Boyarin does not cite Hermes in his discussion of this facet of Philos belief. 16 Berlinerblau, 348. All three of these quotations occur on this page. 53

PAGE 54

arrayed not just against Arian co religionists, but against pagan Hermetists and (through the work of Boyarin) Judaeo-Christians as well. One final question he asks is does the heretical impulse incline to appear among dominant or subaltern strata? Here, the Corpus may prove the most intriguing because it suggests that the proce ss of Christian orthodoxy cr eation is a subaltern reaction against a dominant multi-religious background. The path of Corpus references from the tacit incorporation of Lactantius, to the vehe ment attack of Firmicus, to the enlightened negligence of Augustine follows th e growth of orthodox belief from insecure minority to holder of symbolic power separa ting right belief from wrong. Augustines death in 430ce at the hands of the Vandals marks a turning point both for Christianity and the Corpus Hermeticum For Christianity, the year 431ce ended with the Council of Ephesus and a definition of the na ture of Christ that paralleled Augustines foundational concept of Christ as the only mediator. His attack also marked a transition in interpretation of the Corpus from a philosophical alternative to Christianity, to (at best) a supporting legend for its birth.17 Both the philosophical and pract ical aspects of the Hermetica, its magical and alchemical treatises, would surviv e and inform the alchemy of Islam, eventually to arrive in ninth century Byzantium. By the el eventh century, the Hermetic treatises arrived in the hands of Michael Psellus, a Byzantine scholar who despised magi c. It is possible that the collection of Hermetica that makeup the modern Corpus Hermeticum may have been redacted by Psellus to expunge any distasteful magical writings while leaving in tact those philosophical texts that seemed to support the rise of Christianity. Psellus may have inadvertently separated the two branches of Hermetic writing to such a degree that its Late Anti que origins disappeared, allowing 17 Exploring the question of whether Hermeticism really wa s an alternative to Christianity or may have been a failed religion will also be the subject of ongoing research. For a definition of religion including priests, rites, rules, and sacrifices, see Boyarin, 204. For a discussion of magic as the products of a disintegrating religion see A. R. Barb, The Survival of Magic Arts, in The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century ed. Arnaldo Momigliano (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963), 100-125. 54

PAGE 55

55 Renaissance interpreters (much to the chagrin of Augustine) to push Hermes even farther into the past, strengthening his claim on authorit y, and their fascination for his writing.18 Returning to 1463ce and the desk of Marsilio Ficino, the Corpus entered a new phase of its long career, becoming the handbook of the Renaissance Magus in the flood of books made possible by the printing press, but that is a st ory left to another chapter. 18 Copenhaver, xl-xli.

PAGE 56

LIST OF REFERENCES Primary Sources Augustine, trans. David Wiesen. The City of God against the Pagans, Vol. III, Books VIII-XI, Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge : Harvard University Press, 1968). Augustine, trans. Henry Chadwick. Confessions (Oxford: Oxford Univ ersity Press, 1991). Augustine, trans. R. P. H. Green. De Doctrina Christiana (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995). Augustine, trans. W. Watts. St. Augustines Confessions Vol. II, Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge: Harvard University Pres, 1977). Copenhaver, Brian P. Hermetica:The Greek Corpus Hermeticum and the Latin Asclepius in a new English translation w ith notes and introduction (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). Firmicus Maternus, trans. Clarence A. Forbes. The Error of the Pagan Religions in Ancient Christian Writers: The Works of the Fathers in Translation (New York: Newman Press, 1970). Firmicus Maternus, tran s. Jean Rhys Baum. Ancient Astrology Theory and Practice (Park Ridge, New Jersey: Noyes Press, 1975). Harrison, Stephen, John Hilton, and Vincent Hunink. Apuleius: Rhetorical Works (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001). Iamblichus. De Mysteriis ed. Emma C. Clarke, John M. Dill on, & Jackson P. Hershbell (Leiden: Brill, 2004). Lactance. Institutions Divines in Sources Chretiennes No 337, ed. Pierre Monat (Paris: Les editions Du Cerf, 1987). Lactantius. trans. McDonald, Mary Francis. Lactantius: The Divine Institutes, Books I-VII in The Fathers of the Church, Vol. 49 (Washington D. C.: The Ca tholic University of America Press, 1964). Lactantius, trans. McDonald, Mary Fran cis. Lactantius: Minor Works in The Fathers of the Church, Vol. 54 (Washington D. C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1965). Marcellinus, Ammianus. The Later Roman Empire:(AD 354-378) (London: Penguin Classics, 1986). The Nag Hammadi Library in English trans. by members of the Coptic Library Project of the Institute for Antiquity and Christianity, Jame s M. Robinson, director (New York: Harper & Row, 1977). 56

PAGE 57

Pharr, Clyde, ed. The Theodosian Code and Novels and the Sirmondian Constitutions (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1952). Plato, trans. Desmond Lee. Timaeus and Critias (London: Penguin Books, 1977). Plato, trans. R. E. Allen. The Symposium: The Dialogues of Plato, vol. 2 (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1991). Plotinus, trans. Stephen McKenna. The Enneads (London: Penguin Books, 1991). Schaff, Philip and Henry Wace, eds., St. Augustin: the Writings against the Manichaeans and against the Donatists in Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers Vol. XIII (Peabody, Massachusetts: Hendrickson Publishers, 1994). Secondary Sources Alt, Karen, Man and Daimones: do the daimons influence mans life?, in The Philosopher and Society in Late Antiquity: Essa ys in Honour of Peter Brown ed. Andrew Smith (Swansea, Wales: The Classical Press of Wales, 2005). Assmann, Jan, The Mosaic Distinction: Israel Egypt, and the Invention of Paganism, in Representations No. 56, Special Issue: The Ne w Erudition. (Autumn, 1996): 48-67. Athanassiadi, Polymnia and Michael Frede, Pagan Monotheism in Late Antiquity (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999). Aune, David A., A review of Corpus Hermeticum XIII and Early Christian Literature, in Journal of Biblical Literature 99:4 (Dec., 1980): 641-644. Barb, A. R., The Survival of Magic Arts, in The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century ed. Arnaldo Momigliano (Oxfor d: Clarendon Press, 1963), 100125. Berlinerblau, J., "Toward a Sociolog y of Heresy, Orthodoxy, and Doxa," in History of Religions 40:4 (May, 2001): 327-351. Bourdieu, Pierre, Social Sp ace and Symbolic Power, in Sociological Theory, 7:1 (Spring, 1989): 14-25. Boyarin, Daniel, Border Lines:The Partiti on of Judeo-Christianity (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2004). Brown, Peter, Augustine of Hippo (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2000). Brown, Peter, The Making of Late Antiquity (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975). 57

PAGE 58

Cameron, Averil, The Mediterranean World in Late Antiquity, AD 395-600 (London: Routledge Press, 1991). Chadwick, Henry, Heresy and Orthodoxy in the Early Church (Hampshire, Great Britain: Variorum, 1991). Chadwick, Henry, The Church in Ancient Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001). Chuvin, Pierre, A Chronicle of the Last Pagans trans. B. A. Archer (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990). Curran, John, Pagan City and Christian Capitol: Rome the Fourth Century (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000). Derchain, P. LAuthenticit de linspiration gyptienne dans le Corpus Hermeticum in Revue de l'histoire des religions 161 (1962) : 175-198. Digeser, Elizabeth DePalma, The Making of a Christian Empire: Lactantius & Rome (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2000). Digeser, Elizabeth DePalma, Lactantius, Porphy ry, and the Debate over Religious Toleration, in The Journal of Roman Studies 88 (1998): 129-146. Dodds, E. R., Pagan and Christian in an Age of Anxiety: Some Aspects of Religious Experience from Marcus Aurelius to Constantine (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965). Douglas, Mary, Natural Symbols:Explorations in Cosmology (New York: Pantheon Books, 1982). Drake, H. A., Constantine and the Bishops: The Politics of Intolerance (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2000). Drake, H. A., Firmicus Maternus and the Politics of Conversion, in Qui Miscuit Utile Dulci: Festschrift Essays for P aul Lachlan MacKendrick (Wauconda, Illinois: Bochazy-Carducci Publishers, 1998). Dufault, Olivier, Magic and Religio n in Augustine and Iamblichus, in Religious Identity in Late Antiquity ed. Robert M. Frakes and Elizab eth DePalma Digeser (Toronto: Edgar Kent, Inc., Publishers, 2006). Ebeling, Florian, The Secret History of Hermes Trisme gistus: Hermeticism from Ancient to Modern Times (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2007). Edwards, Mark, The Flowering of Latin Apologetic: Lactantius and Arnobius, in Apologetics in the Roman Empire (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999). Festugire, A. J., La rvlation dHermes Trismgiste 3 vols. 2nd ed. (Paris: LesBelles Lettres, 1950). 58

PAGE 59

Fishur, Arthur L., Lactantius Ideas Relating Christian Trut h and Christian Society, in The Journal of the History of Ideas 43:3 (Jul. Sep., 1982): 355-377. Fowden, Garth, The Egyptian Hermes:A Historical Approach to the Late Pagan Mind (Princeton: Princeton Un iversity Press, 1993). Fowden, Garth, Empire to Commonwealth: Consequences of monotheism in late antiquity (Princeton: Princeton Un iversity Press, 1993). Fowden, Garth, Late Antique Paganism Reasoned and Revealed, in The Journal of Hellenic Studies ,71 (1981): 178-182. Fowden, Garth, The Pagan Holy Man in Late Antique Society, in The Journal of Hellenic Studies 102 (1982): 33-59. Fox, Robin Lane, Pagans and Christians (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1986). Frankfurter, David, Religion in Roman Egypt:Assimilation and Resistance (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998). Geffcken, Johannes, The Last Days of Greco-Roman Paganism (Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company, 1978). Graf, Fritz, Magic in the Ancient World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997). Graf, Fritz, Augustine and Magic, in The Metamorphosis of Magic fr om Late Antiquity to the Early Modern Period ed. Jan N. Bremmer and Jan R. Veenstra (Leuven: Peeters, 2002), pp. 87-104. Grese, William C., Corpus Hermeticum XIII and Early Christian Literature (Leiden: Brill, 1979). Hanson, R. P. C., The Search for the Christian Doctrine of God: The Arian Controversy 318-381 (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1988). Herrin, Judith, The Formation of Christendom (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988). Hunink, Vincent, Apuleius and the Asclepius, in Vigiliae Christianae 50:3 (1996), 288-308. Hunink, Vincent, Apuleius, Pudent illa, and Christianity, in Vigiliae Christianae, 54:1 (2000): 80-94. Hunink, Vincent, 'Apuleius, qui nobis Afris afer est notior': Augustine's polemic against Apuleius in De Civitate Dei, in Scholia: Studies in Classical Antiquity 12 (2003), 82-95. Irvin, Dale T. and Scott W. Sunquist ed., History of the World Christian Movement, Volume I: Earliest Christianity to 1453 (Maryknowll, New York: Orbis Books, 2004). 59

PAGE 60

Kingsley, Peter, Poimandres:The Etymology of the Name and the Origins of the Hermetica, in Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 56 (1993): 1-24. Klingshirn, William E., Divination and the Disc plines of Knowledge according to Augustine, in Augustine and the Disciplines: Fr om Cassiciacum to Confessions, ed. Karla Pollmann and Mark Vessey (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005): 113-140. Klingshirn, William E. and Mark Vessey, The Limits of Ancient Christianity: Essays on Late Antique Thought and Culture in Honor of R. A Markus (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1999). Lee, A.D., Pagans & Christians in Late Antiquity: A Sourcebook (London: Routledge Press, 2000). Luck, George, Ancient Pathways and Hidden Pursuits: Religion, Morals, and Magic in the Ancient World (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2000). MacMullen, Ramsey, Christianizing the Roman Empire, A.D. 100-400 (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984). Mah, Jean-Pierre, Herms en Haute-Egypte: Le fragment du discours parfait et les dfinitions hermtiques armniennes Vol II (Quebec: Presses de L'Universite Laval, 1982). Mah, Jean-Pierre, Preliminary Remarks on the Demotic Book of Thoth and the Greek Hermetica, in Vigiliae Christianae 50:4 (1996): 353-363. Markus, Robert A., Augustine on Magic: A Neglec ted Semiotic Theory in Christianity, in Christianity in Relation to Jews, Greeks, and Romans ed. Everett Ferguson (Garland Publishing: New York, 1999), 205 230. Markus, Robert A., The End of Ancient Christianity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). Merlan, P., Plotinus and Magic, in Isis 44 (1954): 341-348. Ogilvie, R. M., The Library of Lactantius (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978). Potter, David, Prophets and Emperors (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994). Quispel, Gilles, Hermes Trismegistus and the Origins of Gnosticism, in Vigiliae Christianae 46:1 (Mar., 1992): 1-19. Quispel, Gilles, The Asclepius: From the Herme tic Lodge in Alexandria to the Greek Eucharist and the Roman Mass, in Gnosis and Hermeticism: From Antiquity to Modern Times ed. Roelf van den Broek and Wouter J. Hanegraff (New York: St ate University of New York Press, 1998), 69-77. 60

PAGE 61

61 Quispel, Gilles, The Original Doctri ne of Valentinus the Gnostic, in Vigiliae Christianae 50:4 (1996): 327-352. Quispel, Gilles, Studies in Gnosticism and Alexandrian Christianity (New York: Brill, 1996). Rebillard, ric, A New Style of Argument in Christian Polemic: Augustine and the Use of Patristic Citations, in The Journal of Early Christian Studies 8:4 (2000): 559-578. Roots, Peter, The De Opificio De: Th e Workmanship of God and Lactantius, in The Classical Quarterly 37:2 (1987): 466-486. Salzman, Michael, Superstitio in the Codex Theodosianus and the Persecution of Pagans, in Vigiliae Christianae, 41:2 (Jun,. 1987): 172-188. Scott, Walter, Hermetica: The Ancient Greek and Latin Wr itings Which Contain Religious or Philosophic Teachings Ascribed to Hermes Trismegistus 4 vols. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924-1936). Scotti, Mariateresa Horsfall, The Asclep ius: Thoughts on a Re-Opened Debate, in Vigiliae Christianae 54:4 (2000): 396-416. Segal, Robert A., The Poimandres as Myth: Scholarly Theory and Gnostic Meaning (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1986). Stark, Rodney, The Rise of Christianity: A Soc iologist Reconsiders History (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996). Stolte, Bernard H., Magic and Byzan tine Law in the Seventh Century, in The Metamorphosis of Magic from Late Antiquity to the Early Modern Period ed. Jan N. Bremmer and Jan R. Veenstra (Leuven: Peeters, 2002), 105 116. Shaw, Gregory, Theurgy and the Soul: The Neoplatonism of Iamblichus (The Pennsylvania University Press: University Park, PA, 1995). Swift, Louis J., Arnobius and Lactantiu s: Two Views of the Pagan Poets, in Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 96 (1965): 439-448. Thorndike, Lynn, A Roman Astrologer as a Historical Source: Julius Firmicus Maternus, in Classical Philology 8:4 (Oct., 1913): 415-435. Valantasis, Richard, ed., Religions of Late Antiquity in Practice (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000). Vessey, Mark, The Forging of Orthodoxy in Lati n Christian Literature: A Case Study, in The Journal of Early Christian Studies 4:4 (1996): 495-513. Yates, Frances, Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964).

PAGE 62

BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH Charles Flowers is a computer programmer by trade, a historian by desire. He first graduated from the University of Florida in 1993 with a bachelors degree in computer engineering. Working as a programmer and th en manager of programmers, Charles was the person who returned after a long days work to pi ck up a book of Medieval history as a form of relaxation. He came to a point in his life when an adventure was needed; a break from the traditional. With the encouragement of friends and family, he broke with the working world in 2005 to enter the rarefied halls of academia. His area of academic interest has steadily moved backward in time from the Medieval period to Late Antiquity, and south from the moist lands of Europe to the deserts of North Africa and the Middle East. The formative pe riod of Early Christianity in the 2nd through 5th centuries holds special interest. Tracing the development a nd separation of Christianity from the Judaic and pagan milieu is his current focus. Working currently with the Corpus Hermeticum and in the future with Julian the Apostate, Iamblichus, and Arius he is also interested in the role of power in defining the concept of orthodoxy. An early versi on of this thesis was first read at the 42nd International Congress on Medi eval Studies in Kalamazoo, Mi chigan in the Spring of 2007. After graduating with a masters degree in history in 2008, Charles entered the PhD program at the University of Florida. Conti nuing his work on religion and power in Late Antiquity, future chapters of a PhD dissertation will include the role of anti-Nicene, pagan, and early Jewish thinkers in the formation of borders between th e orthodox Christian community and the formation of the Other. 62